21.12.2013 Views

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

h ay e k ’ s t h e c o n s t i t u t i o n o f l i b e r t y<br />

r e q u i r e m e n t s o f t h e r u l e o f l aw<br />

<strong>of</strong> new general rules’ must be separate from ‘their application<br />

to particular cases.’ <strong>The</strong>se two functions ‘must be performed<br />

sep arately by two co-ordinated bodies before it can be determined<br />

whether coercion is to be used in a particular case.’ In practice,<br />

this requires ‘independent judges who are not concerned with any<br />

temporary ends <strong>of</strong> government’ (210–11). <strong>The</strong>se judges ‘are bound<br />

by nothing but the law and secured against all pressure by irremovability<br />

and similar safeguards’ (1955: 37). This arrangement<br />

helps to ensure that rules are made because <strong>of</strong> their general significance<br />

and not to fit particular instances.<br />

Judicial decision-making, as Hayek understands it, looks<br />

beyond particular statutes and their intent. In fact, the judge<br />

has no concern with ‘the hidden intentions <strong>of</strong> the maker <strong>of</strong> the<br />

rules’ (ibid.: 37). <strong>The</strong> judge’s task is ‘to discover the implications<br />

contained in the spirit <strong>of</strong> the whole system <strong>of</strong> valid rules <strong>of</strong> law.’<br />

When necessary, he expresses as a general rule ‘what was not<br />

explicitly stated previously in a court <strong>of</strong> law or by the legislator’<br />

(212). Clearly a great deal <strong>of</strong> discernment is required to grasp<br />

the spirit <strong>of</strong> the laws, to determine its implications for the case<br />

at hand, and to express this as a general rule. <strong>The</strong> judge makes<br />

explicit much that the law itself leaves unstated; and inevitably<br />

‘certain general conceptions’ will enter into the judge’s interpretation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the law. Even so, Hayek measures judicial interpretation by<br />

an objective standard, namely ‘what the rules as they have been<br />

promulgated must mean to an impartial observer’ (1955: 37).<br />

<strong>The</strong> separation-<strong>of</strong>-powers doctrine, in some formulations,<br />

prohibits the general legislature from delegating the rule-making<br />

function to other bodies; but Hayek rejects this limitation. From<br />

the standpoint <strong>of</strong> the Rule <strong>of</strong> Law, he sees nothing wrong with<br />

delegating the power <strong>of</strong> making rules ‘to local legislative bodies,<br />

such as provincial assemblies or municipal councils’ or even in<br />

some instances to ‘some non-elective authority,’ so long as this<br />

authority announces these rules prior to their application and<br />

is made to adhere to them. What Hayek objects to in modern<br />

practice is not delegating legislation, but giving authorities ‘power<br />

to wield coercion without rule’ and expecting the courts to accept<br />

the exercise <strong>of</strong> such power unquestioningly (1960: 211–12; 1955:<br />

38–9).<br />

<strong>The</strong> executive, in coercing private citizens, is subject to<br />

legislative rules and to judicial review<br />

<strong>The</strong> primary function <strong>of</strong> the government or executive is to protect<br />

the individual against coercion by others and thus to safeguard for<br />

each individual a secure private sphere. To this end the executive<br />

enjoys a monopoly <strong>of</strong> coercive power. This function is to be distinguished<br />

from the executive’s administrative or policy function,<br />

which is not inherently coercive, but may become so under a<br />

regime <strong>of</strong> central planning. Hayek insists that with the rise <strong>of</strong><br />

the modern bureaucratic state, individual liberty is now mainly<br />

threatened by administrative power (see 202). Thus it is hardly<br />

surprising that <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Liberty</strong> devotes far more attention<br />

to administration than to lawmaking or judging.<br />

Deciding where the executive stands, in relation to the legislature<br />

and to the courts, is, for Hayek, a major problem that is<br />

addressed throughout Parts II and III, especially when matters <strong>of</strong><br />

‘discretion’ and ‘policy’ are discussed. Hayek regards the legislature<br />

and the courts as distinct and separate powers, but he denies<br />

that this is the case with the executive. <strong>The</strong> decisive consideration<br />

here is not the executive’s monopoly <strong>of</strong> coercion, which arguably<br />

126<br />

127

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!