21.12.2013 Views

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

h ay e k ’ s t h e c o n s t i t u t i o n o f l i b e r t y<br />

s t o p p i n g c o e r c i o n i n e m p l o y m e n t<br />

coercion is today the main aim <strong>of</strong> unions’ (275). Having a<br />

monopoly <strong>of</strong> labour is crucial to this aim, for if unions effectively<br />

control all the potential workers, employers must bargain with<br />

them. Unions thus use coercive means ‘to force unwilling workers<br />

into membership and to keep non-members out <strong>of</strong> employment’<br />

(268). If governments followed the Rule <strong>of</strong> Law, they would prevent<br />

coercive labour monopolies; but instead they have sanctioned or<br />

tolerated hostile picketing in large numbers, closed or union shop<br />

contracts, and secondary strikes and boycotts – all techniques<br />

that Hayek would prohibit (274–5, 278–9). Unions get away with<br />

coercive techniques partly because they wield great political influence<br />

and partly because the public mistakenly thinks that union<br />

activities benefit the entire working class. Economists can render a<br />

public service by correcting this misconception (273–4).<br />

Unions claim to benefit all workers by raising the general<br />

level <strong>of</strong> wages. To refute this claim, Hayek builds on a distinction<br />

between real wages and money wages – a distinction that<br />

had been important to his business cycle theory and his critique<br />

<strong>of</strong> Keynesian economics. In a 1942 essay he notes that ‘real wages’<br />

commonly refers to ‘the relation between wages as received by<br />

the worker and the prices <strong>of</strong> the commodities on which he spends<br />

those wages.’ By this definition, which centres on the worker’s<br />

purchasing power, real wages can increase if the prices <strong>of</strong> desired<br />

commodities go down or decrease if their prices go up. Inflation<br />

pushes up money wages but not real wages, since the price <strong>of</strong> the<br />

goods purchased by workers also rises (1948: 252).<br />

Hayek has no doubt that unions can increase workers’ money<br />

wages, but can they increase real wages for all? Hayek’s answer<br />

turns on a distinction between ‘all the employed’ and ‘all wishing<br />

to work.’ By limiting the supply <strong>of</strong> labour, unions might be able to<br />

increase the real wages <strong>of</strong> their own members and perhaps even<br />

those <strong>of</strong> all the employed; but as a result some workers will be<br />

unable to find jobs. As Hayek explains, ‘the real wages <strong>of</strong> all the<br />

employed can be raised by union action only at the price <strong>of</strong> unemployment.’<br />

Taking unemployed workers into account, unions<br />

‘cannot in the long run increase real wages for all wishing to work<br />

above the level that would establish itself in a free market.’ Besides<br />

distorting the wage structure, the practice <strong>of</strong> excluding workers<br />

from highly paid occupations produces inequalities among<br />

workers and amounts to ‘the exploitation <strong>of</strong> the relatively poor<br />

by the better-<strong>of</strong>f.’ Also, while union activities can increase the real<br />

wages <strong>of</strong> employed workers, empirical evidence shows that real<br />

wages ‘have <strong>of</strong>ten risen much faster when unions were weak than<br />

when they were strong.’ Hayek concludes that coercive unionism,<br />

despite its claim to benefit all workers, serves the interest <strong>of</strong> a<br />

particular group. It increases real wages for organised workers,<br />

but pits them against others who ‘will find employment only in<br />

the less highly paid jobs’ or else ‘will not be employed at all’ (270;<br />

cf. 270–71).<br />

An argument heard frequently today is that real wages have<br />

steadily lagged behind society’s overall productivity gains, so that<br />

for workers to receive their just share <strong>of</strong> the fruits <strong>of</strong> economic<br />

growth, the power <strong>of</strong> unions to bargain on their behalf must be<br />

strengthened. This argument assumes that union practices raise<br />

productivity. Hayek undercuts it by insisting that union practices<br />

lower productivity, rather than enhancing it. In most European<br />

countries, unions employ ‘restrictive policies <strong>of</strong> a “make-work”<br />

character’ that ‘necessarily reduce the productivity <strong>of</strong> labor all<br />

around and therefore also the general level <strong>of</strong> real wages’ (271; cf.<br />

272–3).<br />

160<br />

161

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!