21.12.2013 Views

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

h ay e k ’ s t h e c o n s t i t u t i o n o f l i b e r t y<br />

t h e u s e a n d l i m i t s o f k n o w l e d g e<br />

Accounting for order is a central aim <strong>of</strong> Hayek’s political<br />

philosophy, but his discussion <strong>of</strong> it in <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Liberty</strong><br />

is quite diffuse as compared with later presentations, where he<br />

distinguishes quite clearly between the order that men deliberately<br />

make (‘organisation’) and order that forms itself (‘spontaneous<br />

order’). Both kinds <strong>of</strong> order are essential to civilisation (see<br />

1964).<br />

Hayek is widely known for his advocacy <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> spontaneous<br />

order. He briefly discusses the concept itself at two points<br />

in <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Liberty</strong>, although the idea <strong>of</strong> spontaneous<br />

growth is present in his discussions <strong>of</strong> tradition, liberty and<br />

progress. Hayek’s comments about organisation as a source <strong>of</strong><br />

order are scattered elsewhere in the book, so the relationship <strong>of</strong><br />

spontaneous and constructed order is not developed thematically.<br />

Hayek’s first description <strong>of</strong> spontaneous order, though not by<br />

that name, comes in Chapter 4, where he examines the contribution<br />

<strong>of</strong> eighteenth-century British thinkers to our understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> progress. <strong>The</strong>se thinkers, especially David Hume, Adam Smith<br />

and Adam Ferguson, addressed the following question: how can<br />

social order emerge, if not from a designing human intelligence or<br />

that <strong>of</strong> a superior being? In addressing it, they<br />

showed how, in the relations among men, complex and<br />

orderly and, in a very definite sense, purposive institutions<br />

might grow up which owed little to design, which were not<br />

invented but arose from the separate actions <strong>of</strong> many men<br />

who did not know what they were doing. (58–9)<br />

<strong>The</strong> Scots in particular saw that the orderly growth <strong>of</strong> institutions<br />

takes place through ‘adaptive evolution’ or ‘the survival <strong>of</strong><br />

the successful’ (59, 57). Those tools and institutions survive which<br />

have proven themselves superior (60). This insight was central to<br />

the British case for freedom, which held that the value <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

‘consists mainly in the opportunity it provides for the growth <strong>of</strong><br />

the undesigned’ (61).<br />

It must be emphasised that in embracing the idea <strong>of</strong> evolution,<br />

Hayek has in mind social or cultural evolution as anticipated<br />

in the teachings <strong>of</strong> eighteenth-century thinkers, particularly<br />

the Scots, and not physical evolution as taught later by Charles<br />

Darwin and others. What is crucial to cultural evolution is not the<br />

selection and transmission <strong>of</strong> physical characteristics, but rather<br />

the selection and transmission <strong>of</strong> values or rules <strong>of</strong> conduct.<br />

Cultural evolution takes place through a process <strong>of</strong> ‘winnowing<br />

and sifting,’ and where it will lead is unknowable and thus<br />

unpredictable. Certainly it does not exhibit an intelligible law.<br />

Its tendency, however, is to produce orders or structures that<br />

reflect ‘the differential advantages gained by groups from practices<br />

adopted for some unknown and perhaps purely accidental<br />

reasons’ (1979: 155; cf. 153–9, 196–200).<br />

Hayek returns to spontaneous order at the very end <strong>of</strong> Chapter<br />

10, where he draws a parallel between natural and social order.<br />

Often in the physical world we must ‘rely on the spontaneous<br />

adjustments <strong>of</strong> individual elements to produce a physical order.’<br />

For example, we ‘could never produce a crystal or a complex<br />

organic compound if we had to place each individual molecule<br />

or atom in the appropriate place in relation to the others;’ yet<br />

because the individual molecules or atoms obey a law <strong>of</strong> nature,<br />

they will in certain conditions ‘arrange themselves in a structure<br />

possessing certain characteristics’ (160). Hayek reasons that spontaneous<br />

forces can likewise produce human society when individuals<br />

act in accordance with general rules or laws. Lawmakers<br />

60<br />

61

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!