21.12.2013 Views

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

h ay e k ’ s t h e c o n s t i t u t i o n o f l i b e r t y<br />

t h e u s e a n d l i m i t s o f k n o w l e d g e<br />

Hayek had long been interested in the way prices convey information.<br />

In writings dating back to the 1930s, he had emphasised<br />

the indispensability <strong>of</strong> prices to economic life (see 1948: 33–56).<br />

<strong>The</strong> most influential <strong>of</strong> these writings is his 1945 essay ‘<strong>The</strong> Use<br />

<strong>of</strong> Knowledge in Society.’ This essay takes up ‘the economic<br />

problem <strong>of</strong> society’ and argues that it ‘can be solved, and in fact<br />

is being solved, by the price system’ (ibid.: 77, 85). Hayek points<br />

out that rapid adaptation to social change requires knowledge<br />

<strong>of</strong> the particular circumstances <strong>of</strong> time and place; but this knowledge,<br />

which is dispersed among countless individuals, cannot be<br />

concentrated in a single mind or planning board. <strong>The</strong> problem<br />

then is to find a way to put dispersed knowledge to use for everyone’s<br />

advantage. In a free society, the price system solves this<br />

problem by ensuring ‘that the knowledge <strong>of</strong> the particular circumstances<br />

<strong>of</strong> time and place will be promptly utilized.’ Moreover, it<br />

communicates to the individual ‘such further information as he<br />

needs to fit his decisions into the whole pattern <strong>of</strong> changes <strong>of</strong> the<br />

larger economic system’ (83–4). Hayek concludes by observing<br />

that the economic problem is but part <strong>of</strong> a broader one, i.e. the<br />

need for processes to overcome ‘the unavoidable imperfection <strong>of</strong><br />

man’s knowledge’ (91). Indeed, this broader problem ‘arises in<br />

connection with nearly all truly social phenomena, with language<br />

and most <strong>of</strong> our cultural inheritance, and constitutes really the<br />

central theoretical problem <strong>of</strong> all social science’ (88).<br />

Hayek here anticipates the more comprehensive treatment <strong>of</strong><br />

the use <strong>of</strong> knowledge that he <strong>of</strong>fers in <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Liberty</strong><br />

(see 4). As it turns out, attentiveness to prices is one way, but not<br />

the only way, that we overcome the imperfection <strong>of</strong> our knowledge<br />

by making use <strong>of</strong> what others know. In fact, <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>Liberty</strong> has much more to say about imitation and about the<br />

salience <strong>of</strong> moral approval and disapproval than about the price<br />

mechanism.<br />

In the 1945 essay, and sometimes also in <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Liberty</strong>, Hayek employs this interesting formulation: the price<br />

system allows the individual to use knowledge that he does not<br />

possess; prices signal what countless individuals know <strong>of</strong> their<br />

own local situations; and I can use them in my own calculations<br />

without actually possessing the dispersed knowledge that they<br />

reflect. Whether this formulation would also cover our use <strong>of</strong><br />

traditional rules as well as instances <strong>of</strong> communication other than<br />

the price system (imitation, responding to signs <strong>of</strong> approval and<br />

disapproval) is uncertain. In conforming to tradition, arguably<br />

we would possess the rule either as a subconscious habit or as a<br />

conscious precept, although the reasons for the rule – the experiences<br />

from which it originated and through which it survived a<br />

long process <strong>of</strong> cultural selection – are unknown to us and therefore<br />

not in our possession. For the most part rules are followed<br />

blindly, without consideration <strong>of</strong> the reasons for them. <strong>The</strong> same<br />

may be largely true <strong>of</strong> our responses to approval and disapproval.<br />

Hayek does indicate, however, that as social evolution advances,<br />

imitation may come to have an element <strong>of</strong> deliberation and choice.<br />

Knowledge and social order<br />

In daily life we rely on rules and signs and take for granted the<br />

knowledge they make available for our use. By acting on such<br />

knowledge, we are able to carry out our own plans and to anticipate<br />

what to expect from others. All <strong>of</strong> this is to assume that the<br />

social world is orderly, but where does this order come from and<br />

what is its character?<br />

58<br />

59

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!