21.12.2013 Views

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

h ay e k ’ s t h e c o n s t i t u t i o n o f l i b e r t y<br />

i n d i v i d ua l f r e e d o m , c o e r c i o n a n d p r o g r e s s<br />

to that imposed by the state? As Hayek explains it, we conform<br />

to moral rules mostly from habit, but social pressure to do so<br />

is <strong>of</strong>ten intense. J. S. Mill had regarded such conformity as the<br />

most pressing contemporary threat to freedom, greater even<br />

than the threat <strong>of</strong> state coercion (Mill, 1975: 57–69). Hayek is less<br />

concerned than Mill with protecting private conduct ‘from the<br />

pressure <strong>of</strong> opinion or disapproval.’ Mill, in strongly attacking<br />

this so-called moral coercion, ‘probably overstated the case for<br />

liberty’ (146; cf. 435, n. 32). In Hayek’s view, it is better ‘not to<br />

represent as coercion the pressure that public approval or disapproval<br />

exerts to secure obedience to moral rules and conventions’<br />

(146).<br />

Hayek thinks that ‘a free society will function successfully only<br />

if the individuals are in some measure guided by common values;’<br />

and this is why he is willing for society to exert pressure on individuals<br />

to conform to moral rules. Nonetheless, he doesn’t want<br />

this pressure to interfere with the individual’s freedom <strong>of</strong> choice.<br />

We must recognise that ‘each person has his own scale <strong>of</strong> values<br />

which we ought to respect, even if we do not approve <strong>of</strong> it.’ If we<br />

believe in freedom, we will not ‘regard ourselves as the ultimate<br />

judges <strong>of</strong> another person’s values’ or ‘feel entitled to prevent him<br />

from pursuing ends which we disapprove <strong>of</strong> so long as he does not<br />

infringe the equally protected sphere <strong>of</strong> others.’ A society that fails<br />

to recognise these principles ‘can have no respect for the dignity <strong>of</strong><br />

the individual and cannot really know freedom’ (79).<br />

Freedom <strong>of</strong> action<br />

What is to count as coercion, especially the arbitrary kind that<br />

encroaches on individual freedom? Hayek certainly wishes to<br />

protect individuals and their property from physical harm, but<br />

his primary emphasis is on assuring the individual’s freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

action. Inflicting physical harm, or threatening it, is a form <strong>of</strong><br />

coercion, but so is interference with free action. Freedom <strong>of</strong> action<br />

includes economic liberty, but it is wider than this. For Hayek, it<br />

encompasses the individual’s freedom to plan his own life and to<br />

carry out that plan. Recognising that this requires extensive information,<br />

Hayek defines coercion broadly to include the manipulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> a person’s environment by such means as deception<br />

or withholding vital facts. Coercion, in this wider sense, is ‘the<br />

control <strong>of</strong> the essential data <strong>of</strong> an individual’s action by another’<br />

(139).<br />

In extending this freedom to every individual, Hayek implicitly<br />

follows the principle, famously articulated by Kant, that human<br />

individuals are to be regarded as ends and not as a means only. A<br />

person who is coerced no longer pursues his own ends or plan <strong>of</strong><br />

life, but must act according to ends or goals that are imposed by<br />

someone else. In so acting I become merely a means to another’s<br />

end. I still exercise choice, but ‘my mind is made someone else’s<br />

tool, because the alternatives before me have been so manipulated<br />

that the conduct that the coercer wants me to choose becomes<br />

for me the least painful one’ (133). I have been deprived <strong>of</strong> the use<br />

<strong>of</strong> my intelligence and knowledge in the pursuit <strong>of</strong> my own aims<br />

(134).<br />

But why is it beneficial that the individual should be free to<br />

pursue his own ends or life plan? Hayek is somewhat vague about<br />

the benefit that the individual himself gains from such freedom.<br />

He does not justify it as a path to success in amassing property,<br />

winning acclaim, cultivating virtue, or attaining happiness: ‘we<br />

must recognize that we may be free and yet miserable’ (18). Hayek<br />

46<br />

47

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!