21.12.2013 Views

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

h ay e k ’ s t h e c o n s t i t u t i o n o f l i b e r t y<br />

s o c i a l s e c u r i t y, t a x a t i o n a n d t h e r e d i s t r i b u t i o n o f w e a lt h<br />

what is in the community’s interest, which is preventing harm to<br />

its members. Compulsion is justifiable in this case because people<br />

who neglect to make provision ‘would become a charge to the<br />

public’ (286).<br />

Hayek’s proposals, as summarised above, are embedded<br />

in a scathing critique <strong>of</strong> unitary, government-controlled social<br />

security systems, the original <strong>of</strong> which was the ‘social insurance’<br />

arrangement that Otto von Bismarck’s government enacted in<br />

Germany in the 1880s. Although Bismarck did not ban the private<br />

relief agencies that then existed, he decreed that the state would<br />

henceforth be the sole provider <strong>of</strong> such social services through a<br />

unified organisation to which everyone protected had to belong.<br />

<strong>The</strong> German plan went beyond compulsory insurance to require<br />

‘compulsory membership in a unitary organization controlled by<br />

the state’ (287).<br />

<strong>The</strong> German model spread because it was presumed to be the<br />

most efficient and economical way to provide universal coverage.<br />

Hayek grants that this might be true when centralised plans are<br />

first introduced, but holds that relying ‘on the gradual evolution<br />

<strong>of</strong> suitable institutions’ is a better solution in the long run, even if<br />

for a time some needs receive inadequate attention. A centralised<br />

design for social services shuts <strong>of</strong>f ‘the constant re-evaluation <strong>of</strong><br />

available resources’ and leads to long-term inefficiencies (287; cf.<br />

232).<br />

Hayek goes on to argue that compulsory social service<br />

monopolies were mainly attractive to socialists not because <strong>of</strong><br />

their presumed efficiency, but because they provided a means <strong>of</strong><br />

egalitarian redistribution. <strong>The</strong> socialists recognised that a monopolistic<br />

government service could distribute benefits according to<br />

perceived need and also redistribute income from one group to<br />

another, as might seem desirable. <strong>The</strong>se compulsory monopolies<br />

were represented to the public as ‘social insurance,’ but this claim<br />

was deceptive.<br />

Insurance, properly speaking, grants protection only to those<br />

who can claim it through their contributions. Monopolistic social<br />

security programmes, by contrast, enrol those who have not<br />

yet had time to establish a claim. People receive ‘as a matter <strong>of</strong><br />

right what they have only to a small extent paid for.’ Benefits are<br />

not limited to a contractual amount, or even to some necessary<br />

minimum, but reflect a political judgement as to an amount that<br />

would be adequate, regardless <strong>of</strong> a person’s need or contribution.<br />

Unlike genuine insurance, government plans can transfer income<br />

from one group to another. Pension claims, for example, are paid<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the taxes <strong>of</strong> those currently working, and not from income<br />

on capital set aside to honour these claims. Wealth is thus transferred<br />

from the young and productive members <strong>of</strong> society to the<br />

elderly, a result which leads Hayek to speculate that the burden on<br />

the young may in the future become greater than they are willing<br />

to bear (288–9, 292 and 295–7).<br />

Hayek gives several reasons why unitary state systems <strong>of</strong> social<br />

security, as they have developed everywhere, pose a critical threat<br />

to freedom. First, these programmes are necessarily coercive.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y designate government as the monopoly provider <strong>of</strong> certain<br />

services and give administrators broad discretion to distribute<br />

benefits to individuals according to what they are thought to<br />

deserve. Systems <strong>of</strong> state medicine transform doctors into paid<br />

servants <strong>of</strong> the state, subject to instruction by authority as to<br />

the provision <strong>of</strong> medical services (288–90, 300). Second, these<br />

programmes are at odds with a healthy democracy. This is partly<br />

because their very complexity defeats democratic deliberation<br />

152<br />

153

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!