21.12.2013 Views

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

h ay e k ’ s t h e c o n s t i t u t i o n o f l i b e r t y<br />

t h e u s e a n d l i m i t s o f k n o w l e d g e<br />

term, declaring it to be a dangerous and misleading expression that<br />

ought to be avoided. <strong>The</strong> rationalist/anti-rationalist distinction is<br />

replaced by one between two kinds <strong>of</strong> rationalism, which Hayek<br />

calls ‘constructivist’ and ‘critical.’ His own position, and that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

evolutionary tradition from which he draws, is renamed ‘critical<br />

rationalism’ – a term borrowed from Karl Popper (1967: 94).<br />

In order to bring out reason’s limits, Hayek <strong>of</strong>fers a critique<br />

<strong>of</strong> reason. This critique moves at two levels, one <strong>of</strong> which is much<br />

more radical than the other. At the less radical level, Hayek insists<br />

on the pervasiveness <strong>of</strong> human ignorance and shows that reason<br />

can neither supply the knowledge required for daily life nor<br />

explain the processes that make such knowledge available for our<br />

use. At a second and more damaging level, he depreciates reason<br />

itself, first by subordinating reason to the subconscious mind and<br />

then by submerging mind into the process <strong>of</strong> civilisation.<br />

Hayek knew that rationalism, both ancient and modern,<br />

had taken its bearings by a natural order whose principles are<br />

constant and intelligible to the human mind. In one way or<br />

another, it had taught that reason can transcend the here and<br />

now, the opinions <strong>of</strong> the time, to apprehend the unchanging<br />

truth <strong>of</strong> things, including the good and beautiful. Ancient and<br />

medieval rationalists in particular had taught that essential qualities<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world itself are captured by the concepts employed in<br />

reasoning. Know ledge <strong>of</strong> nature, especially human nature, would<br />

provide a timeless standard by reference to which human affairs<br />

could be ordered. Hayek regards these rationalist views as both<br />

wrong theoretically and dangerous from a practical standpoint.<br />

He wants to foreclose any appeal to nature that might call tradition<br />

into question, or undercut the existing order, or fuel reckless<br />

change by stimulating a taste for ‘perfectionism.’<br />

Hayek aims to discredit rationalist theories <strong>of</strong> this sort<br />

through his evolutionary account <strong>of</strong> mind. By his account, the<br />

human mind evolved slowly for a million years or more before<br />

reason finally emerged. Even now, our actions depend much more<br />

on habit and unthinking responses to signs than on the kind <strong>of</strong><br />

knowledge that an individual mind ‘consciously manipulates’<br />

(24). Man’s mind is thus ‘a product <strong>of</strong> the civilization in which<br />

he has grown up and … he is unaware <strong>of</strong> much <strong>of</strong> the experience<br />

which has shaped it – experience that assists it by being embodied<br />

in the habits, conventions, language, and moral beliefs which are<br />

part <strong>of</strong> its makeup’ (24). What mind has and will become depend<br />

on the process <strong>of</strong> civilisation. Civilisation preserves and transmits<br />

general rules and beliefs, and the individual mind is a collection<br />

<strong>of</strong> them. This is not to say that the mind is merely passive. Besides<br />

classifying sense data, it has ‘the capacity to restrain instincts.’<br />

Without such restraints, civilisation could never develop (1988:<br />

22; cf. 1979: 160).<br />

Hayek was greatly influenced by the historicisation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

mind that occurred in German thought in the late nineteenth<br />

century – a development that would, over the next century,<br />

transform the way scholars understood human knowing and<br />

reasoning. This was a time when historians and anthropologists<br />

were able to argue, from abundant data, that beliefs and worldviews<br />

vary greatly from one society or civilisation to another. Such<br />

data alone was insufficient, however, to support the claim that the<br />

mind itself changes. For this a theory <strong>of</strong> knowledge was required.<br />

This new theory began from Kant’s principle that ultimate<br />

being is unknowable to reason, because we perceive it only as<br />

filtered through the mind’s categories. Nature, as known to us,<br />

is already a product <strong>of</strong> a mental transformation and not a true<br />

64<br />

65

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!