21.12.2013 Views

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

h ay e k ’ s t h e c o n s t i t u t i o n o f l i b e r t y<br />

r e q u i r e m e n t s o f t h e r u l e o f l aw<br />

makes it more powerful than the legislature and the courts, but<br />

its dependence on the other powers. <strong>The</strong> legislature and the judiciary<br />

are independent <strong>of</strong> each other in that one formulates rules<br />

and the other interprets them. <strong>The</strong> executive, however, is bound<br />

in its coercive actions ‘by rules which prescribe not only when<br />

and where it may use coercion but also in what manner it may do<br />

so.’ Moreover, all <strong>of</strong> its actions <strong>of</strong> this kind are subject to judicial<br />

review. Hayek’s aim here is to hem in the executive, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as its<br />

use <strong>of</strong> coercion is concerned, by subordinating it to legislative<br />

rules, on the one hand, and judicial review, on the other. In this<br />

respect it is not ‘independent’ and therefore not a separate power<br />

(211).<br />

Hayek grants that administrators, like judges, must interpret<br />

legislative rules in order to apply them, but the substance <strong>of</strong> their<br />

interpretation must be subject to review by an independent court.<br />

In such a review, the court will impose a very strict test, deciding<br />

whether the administrative decision is ‘deducible from the rules<br />

<strong>of</strong> law and from those circumstances to which the law refers and<br />

which can be known to the private parties affected’ (1955: 41; 1960:<br />

213–14). When it comes to protecting the individual from coercion<br />

and securing impartial justice, independent courts must have the<br />

last word.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Rule <strong>of</strong> Law safeguards fundamental rights and civil<br />

liberties<br />

Hayek’s case for freedom is not built around the idea <strong>of</strong> individual<br />

rights, but, nonetheless, rights are vital to his account <strong>of</strong><br />

the Rule <strong>of</strong> Law. <strong>The</strong>se are not to be understood as natural rights,<br />

in the Lockean sense, but as rights that have evolved historically<br />

and have found expression in various constitutional provisions.<br />

What can statements <strong>of</strong> rights add to the general argument for<br />

freedom? After all, under ‘a reign <strong>of</strong> freedom the free sphere <strong>of</strong> the<br />

individual includes all action not explicitly restricted by a general<br />

law’ (216). If the individual enjoys the freedom (or right) to do<br />

whatever a general law does not restrict, then what is gained by<br />

enumerating specific rights? And since any enumeration is necessarily<br />

incomplete, isn’t there a danger <strong>of</strong> depreciating rights that<br />

aren’t explicitly recognised? Hayek acknowledges this danger,<br />

but concludes that bills <strong>of</strong> rights have in the past afforded ‘an<br />

import ant protection for certain rights known to be easily endangered’<br />

(216).<br />

In the Cairo Lectures, Hayek identifies the rights associated<br />

with ‘life, liberty, and property,’ along with liberty <strong>of</strong> speech,<br />

religion, the press and assembly, as essential ones; and he stresses<br />

the right to private property in particular, since rules <strong>of</strong> property<br />

determine ‘the boundaries <strong>of</strong> individual private spheres in the<br />

material world, and ways <strong>of</strong> voluntarily changing these boundaries’<br />

(1955: 44). Hayek’s emphasis in <strong>The</strong> <strong>Constitution</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Liberty</strong> is<br />

on how rights are endangered by advancing technologies (216).<br />

He acknowledges the importance <strong>of</strong> procedural safeguards, but<br />

does not expect that they will remain effective if belief in the Rule<br />

<strong>of</strong> Law is weakened (218–19).<br />

How do bills <strong>of</strong> rights serve to protect individual freedom?<br />

Hayek grants that neither legal guarantees <strong>of</strong> fundamental rights<br />

nor constitutional provisions can, in themselves, ‘prevent any<br />

suppression <strong>of</strong> rights by the deliberate action <strong>of</strong> the ultimate legislator’<br />

(217). We recall that the ultimate legislator, in democracies,<br />

is the people, or, more precisely, public opinion or the prevailing<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> justice (1955: 33; 1960: 217). <strong>Constitution</strong>al formulations<br />

128<br />

129

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!