21.12.2013 Views

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

h ay e k ’ s t h e c o n s t i t u t i o n o f l i b e r t y<br />

t h e u s e a n d l i m i t s o f k n o w l e d g e<br />

embodied in a society’s traditions and beliefs as well as in man’s<br />

own unconscious habits. Within the totality <strong>of</strong> such rules or<br />

values, Hayek distinguishes moral values from the rest. Moral<br />

values are rules <strong>of</strong> social conduct; and Hayek insists that we have<br />

‘no choice but to submit’ to such rules, even though we might<br />

not know the rationale for them or see ‘that anything important<br />

depends on their being observed in the particular instance.’ Moral<br />

rules address us as unconditional demands and not as expedient<br />

options: ‘At any one stage <strong>of</strong> our evolution, the system <strong>of</strong> values<br />

into which we are born supplies the ends which our reason must<br />

serve.’ Moral rules thus resemble Kant’s categorical imperative,<br />

but <strong>of</strong> course they are products <strong>of</strong> social evolution and not formulations<br />

<strong>of</strong> the rational will. Even Kantian ethics is derivative from a<br />

prior tradition, i.e. it is an extension <strong>of</strong> ‘the basic idea underlying<br />

the rule <strong>of</strong> law’ (62–6; 196–7).<br />

Ins<strong>of</strong>ar as possible, Hayek wants to make tradition and moral<br />

rules self-legitimising. <strong>The</strong> alternative – to have their legitimacy<br />

dependent on something else – is both unattractive to him and<br />

contrary to his understanding <strong>of</strong> moral experience. He could, for<br />

example, argue that we ought to obey traditional rules because in<br />

doing so we promote a larger end. This would, however, require<br />

the everyday actor to think like a social theorist. As Hayek writes<br />

later, ‘acting individuals usually do not understand’ the ‘functions’<br />

<strong>of</strong> cultural rules that emerge spontaneously (1979: 155). A social<br />

theorist such as Hayek does take an instrumentalist view, because<br />

he sees that obedience to moral rules produces spontaneous order<br />

and also determines whether an evolving society will survive and<br />

prosper in the long run. <strong>The</strong> theorist recognises that ‘the ultimate<br />

decision about what is good or bad will be made not by individual<br />

human wisdom but by the decline <strong>of</strong> the groups that have adhered<br />

to the “wrong” beliefs’ (35–6). Social actors, however, perceive<br />

moral rules as ‘a value in itself ’ and do not require instrumentalist<br />

or expedient reasons for obeying them.<br />

Another way to legitimise traditional rules would be to seek<br />

support from religion, but Hayek, as a scientist, had refused<br />

throughout his career to take this path. He rejects all causal explanations<br />

that appeal to invisible essences or hidden spiritual forces,<br />

since these amount to superstition. Nevertheless, he concedes that<br />

there are ‘good reasons why any person who wants to live and act<br />

successfully in society must accept many common beliefs, though<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> these reasons may have little to do with their demonstrative<br />

truth.’ This requirement ‘applies to all our values,’ but ‘it<br />

is most important in the case <strong>of</strong> moral rules <strong>of</strong> conduct’ (64–5).<br />

In this guarded and even cryptic statement, Hayek is silent<br />

as to whether these ‘common beliefs’ have a religious character<br />

and whether they might serve to legitimise the moral rules to<br />

which they are attached. Much later, in <strong>The</strong> Fatal Conceit, Hayek<br />

addresses these issues directly. He wonders whether he has<br />

underestimated the role <strong>of</strong> religious belief in sustaining beneficial<br />

customs: ‘even an agnostic ought to concede that we owe our<br />

morals, and the tradition that has provided not only our civilization<br />

but our very lives, to the acceptance <strong>of</strong>’ claims that are scientifically<br />

unacceptable, such as those advanced by religion’ (1988: 137).<br />

In an appendix, he cites favourably Sir James Frazer’s argument<br />

that superstition rendered humanity a great service by protecting<br />

marriage and private property (ibid.: 157). Of course, traditional<br />

rules cannot be self-legitimising if they must depend on the<br />

authority <strong>of</strong> religion (or superstition) to uphold their authority.<br />

Hayek seeks not only to describe the role that values play<br />

in social life, but above all to justify a particular set <strong>of</strong> values, as<br />

72<br />

73

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!