21.12.2013 Views

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

h ay e k ’ s t h e c o n s t i t u t i o n o f l i b e r t y<br />

e c o n o m i c p o l i c y a n d t h e r u l e o f l aw<br />

Policies measured by expediency<br />

For policies that are compatible with the Rule <strong>of</strong> Law and the<br />

requirements <strong>of</strong> a free society, the question is whether their<br />

benefits are worth their cost. A wide range <strong>of</strong> activities, universally<br />

undertaken by governments, fall into this category. Some<br />

<strong>of</strong> these furnish information that individuals need to plan their<br />

lives. Government’s most important function here is providing<br />

‘a reliable and efficient monetary system,’ but scarcely less<br />

import ant ‘are the setting <strong>of</strong> standards <strong>of</strong> weights and measures;<br />

the providing <strong>of</strong> information gathered from surveying, land registration,<br />

statistics, etc; and the support, if not also the organization,<br />

<strong>of</strong> some kind <strong>of</strong> education.’ Other policies aim to provide<br />

more material services. <strong>The</strong>se include sanitary and health services,<br />

road construction and maintenance, urban amenities, and ‘public<br />

works’ generally (223).<br />

Hayek does not favour passive government, but rather one<br />

that seeks many benefits for the community. While he shares<br />

the ‘strong presumption against government’s actively participating<br />

in economic efforts,’ he nonetheless states that the ‘old<br />

formulae <strong>of</strong> laissez faire or non-intervention do not provide us<br />

with an adequate criterion for distinguishing between what is<br />

and what is not admissible in a free system’ (221, 231; cf. 257–8).<br />

As he explains, ‘it is the character rather than the volume <strong>of</strong><br />

government activity that is important.’ In economic matters, for<br />

example, an active government that assists the spontaneous forces<br />

<strong>of</strong> the market is preferable to a less active one that does the wrong<br />

things. In this regard he sees himself as following the best <strong>of</strong> the<br />

classical liberals, such as Adam Smith (220–22).<br />

While Hayek does not object to government providing many<br />

services, he does insist strongly on two points. First, these services<br />

must be available to all. No citizen can be excluded arbitrarily<br />

from their enjoyment. Second, government must not forcibly<br />

monopolise the provision <strong>of</strong> these services or enjoy any special<br />

advantage in <strong>of</strong>fering them. If possible private suppliers must be<br />

allowed to compete with government enterprise, or at least the<br />

door must not be shut to them. Both arbitrary exclusion and sheltered<br />

monopoly make state coercion impermissible.<br />

<strong>The</strong> community’s interest<br />

<strong>The</strong> highest standard for judging policy is neither the Rule <strong>of</strong><br />

Law nor expediency, but the interest <strong>of</strong> the community. As noted<br />

earlier, government can in emergencies suspend individual rights<br />

if the community’s interest requires it. In ‘normal’ times, government,<br />

acting within the Rule <strong>of</strong> Law, pursues an expedient course;<br />

but expedient actions must aim towards an end, which ultimately<br />

is the community’s interest.<br />

What policy measures can be justified by expediency, especially<br />

when it comes to coercing individuals? Some <strong>of</strong> Hayek’s<br />

formulations suggest that governmental coercion must be limited<br />

to cases where individuals have violated the law, especially by<br />

harming others: ‘Under the rule <strong>of</strong> law, government can infringe<br />

a person’s protected private sphere only as punishment for<br />

breaking an announced general rule’ (206). This statement would<br />

indicate that only lawbreakers need fear government’s coercive<br />

hand. As Hayek proceeds, however, it becomes clear that governmental<br />

coercion need not be a form <strong>of</strong> punishment. Government<br />

can coerce even law-abiding individuals if the community’s<br />

interest requires it, so long as it does so in conformity to a general<br />

rule and allows for review by independent courts (225).<br />

138<br />

139

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!