26.02.2013 Views

Commentary on Theories of Mathematics Education

Commentary on Theories of Mathematics Education

Commentary on Theories of Mathematics Education

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

On Networking Strategies and <strong>Theories</strong>’ Compatibility 533<br />

out the rectangle with the largest area) was expected to show no manipulati<strong>on</strong>s, as<br />

it is such a case <strong>of</strong> introducti<strong>on</strong>. But that hypothesis was refuted by the data (the<br />

transcript and the video record <strong>of</strong> that scene); the introducti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> that mathematical<br />

method was interwoven with a use <strong>of</strong> Derive.<br />

A use <strong>of</strong> empirically rich theories is characteristic, or even necessary, for quantitative<br />

research as the hypotheses to be formulated need a ground they can be deduced<br />

from. Within qualitative research drawing up<strong>on</strong> such theories may go bey<strong>on</strong>d<br />

expectati<strong>on</strong>s. Literature <strong>on</strong> methodology for this branch <strong>of</strong> research (Kelle<br />

and Kluge 1999) even points to the risk that categories having well-defined properties<br />

and refutable hypotheses involving them could dominate and interfere with the<br />

intended “inclusive” rec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> reality. However, it is not necessary to use<br />

empirically rich theories as it is d<strong>on</strong>e in quantitative research (Hempel 1965); a researcher<br />

is not obliged to restrict her/himself to an examinati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> certain, refutable<br />

hypotheses formulated in advance. Apart from that, in my case this would never<br />

have d<strong>on</strong>e. For instance, the rec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> the way <strong>of</strong> addressing and clarifying<br />

manipulati<strong>on</strong> issues that c<strong>on</strong>tributed much to my small, grounded theory about<br />

computer-based mathematics classrooms could not be accomplished just by checking<br />

hypotheses about the mere modes <strong>of</strong> activities.<br />

My study shows that empirically empty and empirically rich theories can be c<strong>on</strong>nected,<br />

and, moreover, that this c<strong>on</strong>stellati<strong>on</strong> has led to a satisfying result. But what<br />

is the specific benefit <strong>of</strong> combining theories <strong>of</strong> both kinds?<br />

To begin with, qualitative studies prefer theories that lack empirical substance.<br />

This reflects the idea that the reality they can analyze is a reality already interpreted<br />

by the members <strong>of</strong> society, and, accordingly, research should take those interpretati<strong>on</strong>s<br />

in account as a starting-point for analysis (Schwandt 2000). Empirically empty<br />

theories corresp<strong>on</strong>d with that positi<strong>on</strong> because they just provide perspectives from<br />

which data can be looked at and do not postulate the properties <strong>of</strong> the phenomena<br />

that will be perceived from those perspectives. These have the role <strong>of</strong> “sensitizing<br />

c<strong>on</strong>cepts” (Blumer 1954). Literature (including that in mathematics educati<strong>on</strong>) gives<br />

evidence that a synthesis <strong>of</strong> solely empirically empty theories has proven very fruitful.<br />

To menti<strong>on</strong> simply <strong>on</strong>e study that draws up<strong>on</strong> the micro-sociological theories<br />

I have used: Voigt’s (1989) rec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> the social c<strong>on</strong>stituti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> a patterned<br />

mathematical practice in classrooms is a prominent example. So it would be presumptuous<br />

to assert a general superiority <strong>of</strong> a mixed combinati<strong>on</strong>. The respective<br />

empirical loads <strong>of</strong> theories do not matter in their synthesis in the sense that the<br />

loads are decisive for the quality <strong>of</strong> the result.<br />

However, c<strong>on</strong>necting theories that differ in that respect has a positive effect <strong>on</strong><br />

the very development <strong>of</strong> a grounded theory; <strong>on</strong> its “verificati<strong>on</strong>”, to be more precise.<br />

This term refers to the check procedure for hypotheses and their relati<strong>on</strong>ships within<br />

their applicati<strong>on</strong> to further data. It is a moot point am<strong>on</strong>g the authors <strong>of</strong> grounded<br />

theory whether or not this has to be d<strong>on</strong>e in a deliberately carried out examinati<strong>on</strong>:<br />

by predicating certain events and checking whether or not they occur in the data.<br />

According to Glaser (1978), such an explicit verificati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> statements is not necessary<br />

because deducti<strong>on</strong>s from the evolving theory are always checked by further<br />

data, and, c<strong>on</strong>sequently, a verificati<strong>on</strong> already takes place within the ordinary procedure.<br />

From Strauss’ point <strong>of</strong> view (1987), however, an explicit verificati<strong>on</strong> is a

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!