26.02.2013 Views

Commentary on Theories of Mathematics Education

Commentary on Theories of Mathematics Education

Commentary on Theories of Mathematics Education

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<str<strong>on</strong>g>Commentary</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Theories</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Mathematics</strong> Educati<strong>on</strong>: Is Plurality a Problem? 113<br />

Communicati<strong>on</strong> and ‘Translati<strong>on</strong>’ Between Discourses<br />

Another problématique linked to the horiz<strong>on</strong>tal structure and weak grammar relates<br />

to the possibilities <strong>of</strong> ‘translati<strong>on</strong>’ between the different discourses. Plurality might<br />

indeed be a problem when research outcomes are to be integrated. Moore (2006,<br />

p. 40) argues, while a horiz<strong>on</strong>tal knowledge structure with a str<strong>on</strong>g grammar makes<br />

translati<strong>on</strong> possible, <strong>on</strong>e with a weak grammar does not. In the first, there is no break<br />

in the language, because str<strong>on</strong>g grammar aims at the integrati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> language rather<br />

than the accumulati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> languages. “Horiz<strong>on</strong>tal discourses with a weak grammar<br />

are established through a process <strong>of</strong> reinterpretati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the empirical more than<br />

through theoretizati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> objects” (ibid., p. 40). This way <strong>of</strong> knowledge formati<strong>on</strong><br />

(in the sociology <strong>of</strong> educati<strong>on</strong>) was by Bernstein described as being due to a lack <strong>of</strong><br />

proper theorising. A theory, in his c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>, as Moore points out, is a generating<br />

principle for a range <strong>of</strong> possibilities not necessarily yet observed in the empirical.<br />

Moore uses the inventi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> the periodic table as an example. Mendeleev invented<br />

a principle that generated a matrix <strong>of</strong> positi<strong>on</strong>s for the elements (in terms <strong>of</strong> similar<br />

characteristics and <strong>of</strong> atomic weight). The point is that this matrix generated theoretical<br />

possibilities that were not yet empirically realised (<strong>on</strong>ly 63 <strong>of</strong> the 92 elements<br />

were recognised). A theory proper, according to Bernstein, has to include the descripti<strong>on</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> such a generative principle for objects yet to be observed, in additi<strong>on</strong> to<br />

helping to make sense <strong>of</strong> already given empirical instances. Such theorising would<br />

provide the possibility <strong>of</strong> more than <strong>on</strong>ly redescribing the empirical by different languages<br />

based <strong>on</strong> incompatible approaches. However, such a theory need to include<br />

an external language for making sense <strong>of</strong> how a distinct combinati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> features <strong>of</strong><br />

a phenomen<strong>on</strong> under study would look like if encountered in the empirical.<br />

The horiz<strong>on</strong>tal knowledge structure amounts to a plurality <strong>of</strong> theories and eventually<br />

leads to incommensurable parallel discourses, as Lerman points out. This is<br />

indeed a c<strong>on</strong>sequence in case <strong>of</strong> a dogmatic reading <strong>of</strong> ‘imported’ theories. When<br />

incommensurable theories are used to mediate between a phenomen<strong>on</strong> and outcomes<br />

<strong>of</strong> research studies, the results can <strong>on</strong>ly be juxtaposed (see Bergsten and<br />

Jabl<strong>on</strong>ka in print); the interpretati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the outcomes might even be c<strong>on</strong>tradictory.<br />

This is, for example, the case in studies about the difficulties students face when<br />

c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>ted with c<strong>on</strong>textualised tasks. Some see the problem in the students’ lack<br />

<strong>of</strong> using their comm<strong>on</strong> sense (mostly within an individual cognitive framework),<br />

while others point to the students’ problem <strong>of</strong> using too much everyday knowledge<br />

when solving these tasks (mostly from a discursive or sociological perspective) (cf.<br />

Gellert and Jabl<strong>on</strong>ka 2009). Incommensurable or c<strong>on</strong>tradictory interpretati<strong>on</strong>s are<br />

less likely to occur in case <strong>of</strong> undogmatic reading <strong>of</strong> theories or <strong>of</strong> selective pitching<br />

<strong>on</strong> some c<strong>on</strong>cepts to guide data analysis. The theoretical hybrids produced by<br />

such approaches might indeed ease the communicati<strong>on</strong> across discourses. There are<br />

also examples <strong>of</strong> theory recepti<strong>on</strong> that in the l<strong>on</strong>g run amounts to increased use <strong>of</strong><br />

some key c<strong>on</strong>cepts without full recogniti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> the basic principles <strong>of</strong> a theory. As<br />

an example, embodied cogniti<strong>on</strong> found its way into mathematics educati<strong>on</strong> during<br />

the 90ies in two ‘waves’, though the remaining impact <strong>on</strong> the field seems to be an<br />

increased acknowledgement <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>of</strong> the roles <strong>of</strong> bodily based metaphor and gesture<br />

for mathematical cogniti<strong>on</strong> (Bergsten 2008).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!