26.02.2013 Views

Commentary on Theories of Mathematics Education

Commentary on Theories of Mathematics Education

Commentary on Theories of Mathematics Education

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<str<strong>on</strong>g>Commentary</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> Knowing More Than We Can Tell 615<br />

tacit, covert? Could I reaccess it if I needed to? Polanyi’s examples are <strong>of</strong>ten about<br />

physiological and perceptual knowledge, and in his 1962 Terry Lectures he came<br />

out with this very clear asserti<strong>on</strong> about embodied knowing: “by elucidating the way<br />

our bodily processes participate in our percepti<strong>on</strong>s we will throw light <strong>on</strong> the bodily<br />

roots <strong>of</strong> all thought, including man’s highest creative powers” (1966, p. 15).<br />

A number <strong>of</strong> Sinclair’s examples point to the potential significance <strong>of</strong> gesture<br />

for mathematics and for teachers <strong>of</strong> mathematics to attend to, both in themselves<br />

and in their students. What does the body know about the object being drawn, for<br />

instance? What does the hand know (or what is it supposed to learn) from the use<br />

<strong>of</strong> so-called ‘manipulatives’ (with the Latin word manus for ‘hand’ lurking right<br />

inside this word—see Pimm 1995)? We have two words for ways <strong>of</strong> using the ear<br />

(listening and hearing), two for the eye (looking and seeing), and two for the hand<br />

(feeling and touching). Listening, looking and feeling all refer to going out to the<br />

world, searching. But ‘feeling’ has a far broader metaphoric c<strong>on</strong>notati<strong>on</strong> than either<br />

listening or looking.<br />

TheTact<strong>of</strong>theTactile<br />

The c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong>s Sinclair makes between gesture and diagram (which, up to twenty<br />

years ago or so, also entailed a distincti<strong>on</strong> between the dynamic and the static) drawing<br />

<strong>on</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> Gilles de Châtelet and Brian Rotman are intriguing to say the<br />

least. It brought to mind a not-much-referenced part <strong>of</strong> a chapter in the early work<br />

<strong>of</strong> Martin Hughes (1986) in his book Children and Number. This work involved<br />

children aged between three and seven engaging individually in a number <strong>of</strong> tasks,<br />

initially c<strong>on</strong>cerned with their making <strong>of</strong> marks <strong>on</strong> paper attached to identical tins to<br />

help the child know which tin had which number <strong>of</strong> cubes in it. In Chap. 5, Children’s<br />

Inventi<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> Written Arithmetic, he classifies young children’s written number<br />

symbolism (all very distanced, with no human representati<strong>on</strong> in the main) into four<br />

categories. But towards the end, in a secti<strong>on</strong> entitled ‘Children’s representati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

additi<strong>on</strong> and subtracti<strong>on</strong>’ (pp. 72–75), the pages suddenly explode with drawn active<br />

hands, reaching for or pushing, holding or touching the objects (the drawn ‘cubes’<br />

that are the objects <strong>of</strong> the arithmetic).<br />

Just like the Italian Futurists, endeavouring to evoke speed and moti<strong>on</strong> in their<br />

paintings as characteristic <strong>of</strong> the new age in the early twentieth century, so these<br />

children imbue their work <strong>on</strong> paper with the dynamic <strong>of</strong> human hands (sometimes<br />

disembodied, sometimes attached to arms; sometimes from the left, sometimes the<br />

right and even a couple operating from the top <strong>of</strong> the page). In <strong>on</strong>e instance, the<br />

undifferentiated arm extends for an impossible length right to the edge <strong>of</strong> the paper,<br />

the drawer apparently unwilling to chop <strong>of</strong>f the hand to exist by itself.<br />

Human mathematical agency abounds in these drawings/diagrams: there is little<br />

doubt in my mind these are the drawer’s own hands we are being shown. The very<br />

last image in the secti<strong>on</strong> is <strong>on</strong>e where the arithmetic ‘objects’ are human soldiers,<br />

marching from the left (with bearskin hats) for additi<strong>on</strong> and from the right (Légi<strong>on</strong>naires!)<br />

for subtracti<strong>on</strong>. These people are presumably self-motivating, no puppeteer’s<br />

hands are present. (Their signifying directi<strong>on</strong>ality also brought to mind the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!