26.02.2013 Views

Commentary on Theories of Mathematics Education

Commentary on Theories of Mathematics Education

Commentary on Theories of Mathematics Education

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

358 G. Harel<br />

Through such repeated experience, which begins in early childhood, our hypothesis<br />

evaluati<strong>on</strong> becomes dominantly empirical; that is, the pro<strong>of</strong>s that we produce to<br />

ascertain for ourselves or to persuade others become characteristically inductive or<br />

perceptual. If, during early grades, our judgment <strong>of</strong> truth in mathematics c<strong>on</strong>tinues<br />

to rely <strong>on</strong> empirical c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s, the empirical pro<strong>of</strong> scheme will likely dominate<br />

our reas<strong>on</strong>ing in later grades and more advanced classes, as research findings clearly<br />

show (Harel and Sowder 2007). While unavoidable, the extent <strong>of</strong> the dominance <strong>of</strong><br />

the empirical pro<strong>of</strong> scheme <strong>on</strong> people is not uniform. Children who are raised in an<br />

envir<strong>on</strong>ment where sense making is encouraged and debate and argumentati<strong>on</strong> are<br />

an integral part <strong>of</strong> their social interacti<strong>on</strong> with adults are likely to have a smoother<br />

transiti<strong>on</strong> to deductive reas<strong>on</strong>ing than those who are not raised in such an envir<strong>on</strong>ment.<br />

A simple, yet key, observati<strong>on</strong> here is this: the arguments children produce to<br />

prove asserti<strong>on</strong>s and account for phenomena in everyday life impact the kind and<br />

robustness <strong>of</strong> the pro<strong>of</strong> schemes they form. Pro<strong>of</strong>s, as was explained earlier, are<br />

ways <strong>of</strong> understanding associated with the mental act <strong>of</strong> proving, and pro<strong>of</strong> schemes<br />

are ways <strong>of</strong> thinking associated with the same act. Hence, a generalizati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> this<br />

observati<strong>on</strong> is: for any mental act, the ways <strong>of</strong> understanding <strong>on</strong>e produces impact<br />

the quality <strong>of</strong> the ways <strong>of</strong> thinking <strong>on</strong>e forms.<br />

Of equal importance is the c<strong>on</strong>verse <strong>of</strong> this statement; namely: for any mental act,<br />

the ways <strong>of</strong> thinking <strong>on</strong>e has formed impact the quality <strong>of</strong> the ways <strong>of</strong> understanding<br />

<strong>on</strong>e produces. The latter statement is supported by observati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>of</strong> students’<br />

mathematical behaviors, for example, when proving. As was indicated earlier, the<br />

empirical pro<strong>of</strong> scheme does not disappear up<strong>on</strong> entering school, nor does it fade<br />

away effortlessly when students take mathematics classes. Rather, it c<strong>on</strong>tinues to<br />

impact the pro<strong>of</strong>s students produce.<br />

This analysis points to a reciprocal developmental relati<strong>on</strong>ship between ways <strong>of</strong><br />

understanding and ways <strong>of</strong> thinking, which is expressed in the Duality Principle.<br />

The principle is implied from the Interdependency Premise. To see this, <strong>on</strong>e <strong>on</strong>ly<br />

needs to recognize that a pers<strong>on</strong>’s ways <strong>of</strong> thinking are part <strong>of</strong> her or his view <strong>of</strong><br />

the world, and that a pers<strong>on</strong>’s ways <strong>of</strong> understanding are manifestati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>of</strong> her or<br />

his acti<strong>on</strong>s. Specifically, the statement, ways <strong>of</strong> understanding students produce are<br />

impacted by the ways <strong>of</strong> thinking they possess, is an instantiati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> the premise’s<br />

asserti<strong>on</strong> that humans’ acti<strong>on</strong>s are induced and governed by their views <strong>of</strong> the world,<br />

whereas the statement, students develop ways <strong>of</strong> thinking through the producti<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

ways <strong>of</strong> understanding, is an instantiati<strong>on</strong> <strong>of</strong> the premise’s asserti<strong>on</strong> that humans’<br />

views <strong>of</strong> the world are formed by their acti<strong>on</strong>s. Furthermore, the C<strong>on</strong>text Dependency<br />

Premise adds a qualificati<strong>on</strong> to this statement: ways <strong>of</strong> thinking bel<strong>on</strong>ging to<br />

a particular discipline best develop from or are impacted by ways <strong>of</strong> understanding<br />

bel<strong>on</strong>ging to the same discipline.<br />

The Necessity Principle. This principle asserts:<br />

For students to learn the mathematics we intend to teach them, they must have a<br />

need for it, where ‘need’ here refers to intellectual need.<br />

There is a lack <strong>of</strong> attenti<strong>on</strong> to students’ intellectual need in mathematics curricula<br />

at all grade levels. C<strong>on</strong>sider the following two examples: After learning how

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!