26.02.2013 Views

Commentary on Theories of Mathematics Education

Commentary on Theories of Mathematics Education

Commentary on Theories of Mathematics Education

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Knowing More Than We Can Tell 599<br />

in particular, the case in which the real values <strong>of</strong> an infinite sequence do not get<br />

closer and closer to a single real value as n increases, but “oscillate” between two<br />

fixed values. When he utters the word “oscillate,” his right hand, with the palm towards<br />

the left, and with his index and thumb touching, moves his high right arm horiz<strong>on</strong>tally<br />

back and forth. Núñez argues that the gesture and linguistic expressi<strong>on</strong> are<br />

telling different stories, with the gesture referring to fundamentally dynamic aspects<br />

<strong>of</strong> the mathematical idea. Harris might argue that the word “oscillate” is already<br />

metaphorical and already points back in time to a spatio-temporal c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>—and<br />

that therefore, the linguistic and gestural expressi<strong>on</strong>s are actually quite similar. In<br />

fact, Harris suggests the need for further gesture research involving mathematical<br />

ideas and c<strong>on</strong>cepts that are not already as temporal as limits and c<strong>on</strong>tinuity. 1<br />

Brian Rotman (2008) sums up Châtelet’s positi<strong>on</strong> as follows: “If <strong>on</strong>e accepts<br />

the embodied—metaphorical and gestural—origins <strong>of</strong> mathematical thought, then<br />

mathematical intuiti<strong>on</strong>s becomes explicable in principle as the unarticulated apprehensi<strong>on</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> precisely their embodiment” (p. 38). For Rotman, intuiti<strong>on</strong> thus becomes<br />

a “felt c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> to [the] body” (p. 38). And maybe Weil’s pleasure is <strong>on</strong>e <strong>of</strong> rec<strong>on</strong>necting<br />

to the body. Certainly, in ruing the inevitable take-over, Weil suggests that<br />

there is as much pleasure in this as there is in solving a problem or finding a pro<strong>of</strong>:<br />

“A day comes when the illusi<strong>on</strong> vanishes: presentiment turns into certainty [...]<br />

Luckily, for researchers, as the fogs clear at <strong>on</strong>e point, they form again at another”<br />

(p. 52).<br />

Drawing <strong>on</strong> interviews with over seventy mathematicians, Le<strong>on</strong>e Burt<strong>on</strong> (2004)<br />

identifies “intuiti<strong>on</strong> and insight” as <strong>on</strong>e <strong>of</strong> the five principal ways in which mathematicians<br />

“come to know.” In a previous piece, which also drew <strong>on</strong> these interviews<br />

(1999), she examines why intuiti<strong>on</strong> and insight have not been nurtured in mathematics<br />

educati<strong>on</strong>. She suggests that <strong>on</strong>e way to nurture intuiti<strong>on</strong>s in problem-solving<br />

c<strong>on</strong>texts is to ask students to engage in “p<strong>on</strong>derings, what ifs, it seems to me that’s,<br />

it feels as thoughs” (p. 30). The metaphoric emphasis <strong>of</strong> Châtelet would demand<br />

that we extend this list to include “it’s like, it’s similar to, it reminds me <strong>of</strong>.” This<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> activity may help bring to the fore the verbal, imagistic, kinetic associati<strong>on</strong>s<br />

that Pimm (1994) argues are so important to meaning: “I believe meaning is partly<br />

about unaware associati<strong>on</strong>s, about subterranean roots that are no l<strong>on</strong>ger visible even<br />

for <strong>on</strong>eself, but are n<strong>on</strong>etheless active and functi<strong>on</strong>ing” (p. 112).<br />

If intuiti<strong>on</strong>s are precisely the unarticulated c<strong>on</strong>sequences <strong>of</strong> embodiment, then it<br />

becomes even more interesting to explore the ways in which our bodies experience<br />

mathematics and, in particular, the extent to which technologies teach our bodies<br />

how to think and feel. To focus <strong>on</strong> just <strong>on</strong>e particular example: how does the link<br />

between gesture and diagram change in dynamic geometry envir<strong>on</strong>ments in which<br />

the gesture no l<strong>on</strong>ger needs freezing and, more, in which the human gesture follows<br />

from the machine <strong>on</strong>e?<br />

I have rearranged and compressed my list <strong>of</strong> covert ways <strong>of</strong> knowing by phasing<br />

out “intuiti<strong>on</strong>” as a primary category and subsuming it instead to the specifically<br />

mathematical endeavour <strong>of</strong> passing from body to sign, through metaphor and<br />

1 Sinclair and Gol Tabaghi (2009) report <strong>on</strong> interviews with mathematicians that involve looking<br />

for evidence <strong>of</strong> fictive moti<strong>on</strong> in n<strong>on</strong>-temporal settings, such as eigenvectors and multiplicati<strong>on</strong>.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!