30.05.2014 Views

The Jewish Historian Flavius Josephus: A Biographical Investigation

The Jewish Historian Flavius Josephus: A Biographical Investigation

The Jewish Historian Flavius Josephus: A Biographical Investigation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

victorious students who proved to be φιλόπονοι, i.e. they had distinguished themselves<br />

precisely in the manner that Justus strove to appear to follow, according to <strong>Josephus</strong>. That<br />

<strong>Josephus</strong> was truly thinking here of the school competitions is apparent from the fact that he<br />

referred to the γύμνασμα ἐν σχολῇ μειρακίων (C. Ap. 1.53) in the same context (cf. p. 20). <strong>The</strong><br />

concept spread from the academic environment to literature, and Nicolaus (F.H.G. 3.350 f.),<br />

when he had brought his work to completion, referred with pride to his φιλοπονία, which<br />

enabled him to accomplish an achievement that would have daunted even a Hercules. Now, if<br />

Justus truly proves to be φιλόπονος in his works – as he had aspired – then his historical work<br />

is accordingly commended to his readership in order to damage the older presentation of<br />

<strong>Josephus</strong> in the same way that the victors in the school competition for φιλοπονία gained an<br />

advantage over their inferior companions. [11] For this reason, such aspiration for the renown<br />

of φιλοπονία is extremely closely connected to disparagement of the opponent, an<br />

opportunity for which Justus also did not overlook.<br />

<strong>Josephus</strong> addresses him in 357, “You have the impudence to claim that you have<br />

recounted the history better (ἄμεινον) than all others.” Justus’ words are produced verbatim<br />

once again by <strong>Josephus</strong> in 359 (εἰ δὲ θαρρεῖς ἄμεινον ἁπάντων συγγεγραφέναι): apparently<br />

they stem from the preface of Justus who, following the example of Anaximenes and<br />

<strong>The</strong>opompus (frg. 25 Grenfell-Hunt), wished to justify right away why he had added a new<br />

presentation to those already in existence. <strong>Josephus</strong> believes that he can repudiate the claim<br />

raised by Justus by demonstrating how inadequate the factual credibility of his writing must<br />

be; thus he reinterprets the ἄμεινον of Justus by the term ἀκρίβεια (e.g. 358; 360 etc.) or<br />

ἀλήθεια (367). Surely this was not what Justus had in mind, for we learn from section 40 that<br />

he had intended to exert his effect by means of his expert rhetorical education. <strong>Josephus</strong><br />

himself must admit to Justus’ mastery of rhetoric (καὶ γὰρ οὐδ’ ἄπειρος ἦν παιδείας τῆς παρ’<br />

Ἕλλησιν), but he accuses Justus of feeling entitled to flout the truth by virtue of this formal<br />

education (ὡς τῷ λόγῳ τούτῳ περιεσόμενος τῆς ἀληθείας). Thus Justus had reproached – we<br />

may again assume in his preface – previously published literature for its stylistic inadequacy;<br />

only he among the authors in question had acquired the necessary Greek culture that enabled<br />

one to write to the full satisfaction of educated readers.<br />

That the key phrase Ἑλληνικὴ παιδεία did in fact appear in Justus’ preface can be<br />

proven in another way: <strong>Josephus</strong> addresses Justus in 359, “If you insolently claim to have<br />

14

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!