16.11.2012 Views

THE SHORT OXFORD HISTORY OF ENGLISH LITERATURE

THE SHORT OXFORD HISTORY OF ENGLISH LITERATURE

THE SHORT OXFORD HISTORY OF ENGLISH LITERATURE

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

passion. Burke may, in his most memorable paragraphs, have mourned the extinction of chivalry in France, but his<br />

main recourse was not to the spirit of the Middle Ages but to the eighteenth-century concept of an equable political<br />

balance, a balance which he finds evident in the existing order of things in Britain.<br />

Paine, Godwin, and the ‘Jacobin’ Novelists<br />

Burke’s attack on the ‘metaphysical abstractions’ on which the evolving Revolution in France was based, and his<br />

related challenge to British apologists<br />

[p. 336]<br />

for the French experiment, were readily taken up. Burke had extended his criticism to include comment on the<br />

Constitutional Society and the Revolution Society, both of them radical clubs supported largely by religious Nonconformists,<br />

men who saw themselves as direct heirs to the spirit of the seventeenth-century English Revolution and<br />

as victims of discriminatory laws. Prominent amongst members were the Unitarian minister, Richard Price (1723-91)<br />

(who had actually provoked Burke’s riposte by preaching a sermon on the need to apply French lessons to Britain),<br />

and a fellow Unitarian, the chemist, Joseph Priestley (1733-1804) (who had his house wrecked by a Birmingham mob<br />

as a result of attempting to celebrate the anniversary of the Fall of the Bastille in 1791). Amongst the most committed<br />

of these radicals, in terms of both his writings and his actions, was the independent republican, Thomas Paine (1737-<br />

1809). Paine’s support for both the American and the French Revolutions had made him friends in these<br />

revolutionary nations and powerful enemies at home (his books were burned by the Public Hangman, but, having been<br />

obliged to flee to Paris in 1792, he was granted the privilege of French citizenship). Paine’s acclaim in Jacobin France<br />

was largely based on his reputation as the trouncer of the tyrant-loving Burke in his book The Rights of Man (1791,<br />

1792). If his book lacks the elegance and the systematic argument of Burke’s, its attack upholds a new faith in<br />

constitutionally defined rights and liberties and renders much of Burke’s creaking pragmatism ridiculous. The<br />

‘poison’ of Burke’s ‘horrid principles’ is countered by a delineation of a despotism which extends beyond the person<br />

of a king into ‘every office and department’ whose petty reflections and abuses of royal power are founded on ‘custom<br />

and usage’.<br />

The circulation of The Rights of Man through a chain of British and Irish radical clubs openly sympathetic to<br />

France (and therefore increasingly hostile to the existing British Constitution) may well have reached hundreds of<br />

thousands. Paine’s active political career in France was less propitious. It was while in prison (and under the shadow<br />

of the guillotine from which he was released only by the fall of Robespierre) that he completed what was once his<br />

most notorious work, The Age of Reason (1794-6). Here the ‘age of Revolutions’ bears a post-Voltairean and post<br />

Jeffersonian fruit, one poisonous to Christianity and atheism alike. The ‘Cult of the Supreme Being’, propagated in<br />

Jacobin France, is developed with a no-nonsense English thrust quite free of Robespierre’s posturing and ritualizing.<br />

Paine dedicated his tract to his ‘fellow-citizens of the United States of America’, but his blunt arguments have<br />

implications well beyond the Quaker libertarianism of Franklin or the non-sectarian aspirations of the American<br />

Constitution. Paine proclaims his theism and a faith in a broad egalitarian morality of ‘doing justice, loving mercy,<br />

and endeavouring to make our fellow-creatures happy’. He rejects all forms of established, defined, or ‘revealed’<br />

religion by treating the nature of ‘revelation’ as if it were little more than hearsay. Scriptural authority is disposed of<br />

with much the same verve. The books of the Old Testament are dismissed as a<br />

[p. 337]<br />

collection of ‘obscene stories ... voluptuous debaucheries ... cruel and torturous executions and unrelenting<br />

vindictiveness’. The Gospels strike him as merely anecdotal mystifications. ‘The Word of God’, he proclaims in<br />

capital letters, ‘IS <strong>THE</strong> CREATION WE BEHOLD’, and God himself stands for ‘moral truth’ not ‘mystery or obscurity’.<br />

William Godwin (1756-1836), born into a strong Dissenting tradition, abandoned both his Calvinist theology and<br />

his Congregationalist ministry in 1783 and assumed the alternative career of journalist and pamphleteer. His interest<br />

in both the dissidence of Dissent and contemporary political developments led to his active participation in the debates<br />

of the Constitutional Society. In 1789 he formed part of the congregation that heard Richard Price’s ‘Discourse on the<br />

Love of our Country’ and he was sufficiently provoked by Burke’s response to it to begin work on what became his<br />

own treatise, the Enquiry Concerning Political Justice (1793). The Enquiry is Godwin’s most systematic theoretical<br />

work. He views human happiness and social well-being as the sole purpose of existence, but unlike Rousseau (whose<br />

influence pervades the work) he looks forward to a gradual melting away of all government to be replaced by a new<br />

system of radical anarchy. A rigid adherence to the leading principle of reason is substituted for Rousseau’s cult of

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!