12.07.2015 Views

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

88 Hippocratic Corpus <strong>and</strong> Diocles of Carystuslike to add a second caveat, which has to do with the nature of polemicalwriting in antiquity. Even if we can find a text A, the contents of whichcompletely correspond with the ideas criticised by the author of anothertext, say, B, <strong>and</strong> a text C which only shows some similarities with whatis criticised in B, the statement that B is consciously opposing A <strong>and</strong> notC can at best remain a plausible hypothesis. For we cannot rule out thepossibility that B is actually aiming at C in a way which is – according to ourst<strong>and</strong>ards – just unfair: he may represent the ideas of his opponent in a verydistorted <strong>and</strong> caricaturist way by ignoring several important specificationsor relevant details, or by isolating separate items from their context. Sucha distortion need not be a manifestation of malevolence; it may also be aresult of the fact that the way in which the author of B views text C is ratherdifferent from our perception of it. Especially in the case of an author, suchas Diocles, whose writings have been lost, we should be very careful notto pretend that we can creep into his skin <strong>and</strong> perceive with his eyes theother text which is supposed to be criticised <strong>and</strong> which represents only avery small part of a literature that must have been of considerable size.These remarks may appear unduly sceptical or a tedious example ofstating the obvious. Yet the practice of ancient polemical writers in caseswhere they do mention their opponents by name <strong>and</strong> in which the writingsof these opponents are preserved as well (e.g. the polemics of Christianwriters such as Origen or Tertullian against the Gnostics), shows that fairpolemics were the exception rather than the rule. 33Fredrich’s identifications are, of course, an extreme example, <strong>and</strong> mostscholars dealing with this fragment have expressed themselves in much morecautious terms. Yet the substantial similarity between Diocles’ criticism ofthe first claim <strong>and</strong> the critical remarks of the author of the Hippocratictext On Regimen 2.39 is accepted, <strong>and</strong> it has been suggested that both OnRegimen 2.39 <strong>and</strong> Diocles are arguing against generalisations of a type thephysician Mnesitheus in fragment 22 Bertier (<strong>and</strong> perhaps also the writerof the Hippocratic text On Affections 55) provides evidence of – which isreinforced by the fact that Galen in the immediate context of this samefragment presents Diocles as disagreeing with Mnesitheus on a relatedsubject (although it is not certain that chronology admits of the possibilitythat Mnesitheus actually was the target in either, or both, of these cases). 3433 On Origen’s polemics against the Gnostics see, for instance, Norelli (1992) <strong>and</strong> Castagno (1992).34 Mnesitheus, fr. 22 Bertier (Athenaeus 3.121 d): ‘Salty <strong>and</strong> sweet flavours all have a relaxing effect onthe belly, while those that are acid <strong>and</strong> sharp release urine. Those that are bitter are rather diuretic,while some of them also have a relaxing effect on the belly. Those that are sour, excretions’( ‘ ’, ‘

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!