12.07.2015 Views

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Aristotle on melancholy 145of association from being disturbed by other bodily movements. The euthuoneiriaof melancholics (referred to here as eustochia, ability to makethe right conjecture, which suggests a greater degree of activity) 27 seems tobe based on the ability to ‘perceive similarities’ ( );on other occasions Aristotle relates this ability to a special natural disposition(phusis or euphuia) <strong>and</strong> considers it an important principle for poetry<strong>and</strong> <strong>philosophy</strong>. 28 Aristotle’s explanation of the prophetic dreams of melancholicsis therefore in line with his remark in Mem. 453 a 15 (quoted above).It is difficult to see how these statements can be reconciled with Insomn.461 a 22–3. In this passage Aristotle brackets melancholics together withthe feverish <strong>and</strong> the intoxicated as examples of people who see confused<strong>and</strong> monstrous images in their sleep <strong>and</strong> whose dreams themselves are notcoherent ( ). The cause of this blurriness is that all these affectionscontain air () <strong>and</strong> therefore produce much movement<strong>and</strong> confusion. 29 It is clear that these remarks are in stark contrast with thecharacterisation of melancholics as ‘having clear dreams’ (euthuoneiroi) inDiv. somn. 463 b 15–17 <strong>and</strong> as ‘hitting the mark’ (eustochoi) in464 a 33,where the clear dreams of the melancholics are explained as a result of theirsensitivity to ‘being subjected to many <strong>and</strong> manifold movements’!Given the close connection between both treatises (Div. somn. 464 b9–10 even refers to Insomn. 461 a 14ff., i.e. to the direct context of thepassage on melancholics), it is highly unlikely that Aristotle was unawareof this contradiction. To solve this problem, B. Effe (1970, 85 n. 49) hassuggested a different interpretation of the word euthuoneiros: not ‘dreamingclearly’, but ‘dreaming rightly’, that is to say, ‘dreaming the truth’. Yeteven if this interpretation of euthuoneiros is adopted, it remains impossibleto square Aristotle’s remark in Insomn. 461 a 22–3 (with its contextof distortion of images in dreams) 30 with the possibility to dream rightly.27 To interpret the difference between the two passages as an antithesis between passive susceptibility<strong>and</strong> active seeking is to a certain extent misleading, for this more active ability also escapes consciousrational control (cf. Mem. 453 a 14ff., in which the word is used, but with the explicit notethat recollection in these people is ‘beyond their control’, ’ . The ‘daemonic’ natureof the effect of the human phusis actually consists in the fact that it escapes rational control, i.e. itis ’ (cf. Somn. vig. 453 b 23–4; Eth. Nic. 1179 b 21ff.)28 464 b 1: 464 b 7 explicitly mentions the perceptionof similarities , but the purpose of this passage is to portray the abilityof the interpreter of dreams to determine the resemblance between dream <strong>and</strong> reality in cases inwhich the dreams are not actually clear. See below (section 6) for the significance of this principlein Aristotle’s views on cognitive psychology.29 30 461 a 10ff.: ...(15)

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!