12.07.2015 Views

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The Methodism of Caelius Aurelianus 305try to compare Caelius Aurelianus with Soranus (or with the fragments ofother Methodists), 38 but this comparison is complicated by the differentstatus of the extant works; for Soranus’ Gynaecia, his only major survivingwork, is a very specialised treatise, <strong>and</strong> a very practical one at that, whereasCaelius’ Acute <strong>and</strong> Chronic Affections deal with what may be called thecentral concern of Methodism, namely the diagnosis <strong>and</strong> treatment of diseases.39 Now we know, for example, from a passage in Caelius Aurelianus 40that the Methodists were keen to distinguish between different specialisedareas within medicine, such as surgery, pharmacology <strong>and</strong> dietetics, <strong>and</strong> toassign the discussion of a particular aspect of a particular disease to onearea rather than another. This strong sense of compartmentalisation is apotential source of discrepancies, <strong>and</strong> hence of apparent inconsistencies,between the ways a certain subject is dealt with in different contexts.Yet also the possible explanation of tensions inherent in Methodism itselfshould be used with some caution. On the one h<strong>and</strong>, historians of ancientmedicine have recently stressed that Methodism is not a <strong>philosophy</strong> but away of doing medicine, <strong>and</strong> a thoroughly practical way of doing medicineat that – though admittedly not without relation to <strong>philosophy</strong> – <strong>and</strong> thisshould make us careful not to approach Methodism as if it were an appliedform of Scepticism. 41 After all, practicability was not the major concern, orindeed the major strength, of Scepticism. On the other h<strong>and</strong>, we shoulddem<strong>and</strong> from Caelius a reasonable degree of consistency <strong>and</strong> systematicity(although we may have to allow for some flexibility in the extent to whichthis is implemented or for potential divergences between theory <strong>and</strong> practice).The point is that doctrinal <strong>and</strong> methodological tensions may, in thecase of Methodism, find their origin in the fact that the primary concernof Methodism is the successful diagnosis <strong>and</strong> treatment of diseases, <strong>and</strong> inthe Methodists’ belief that all issues that are not necessarily related to this(such as the question of what the cause of a disease is, or what its correctdefinition is, or which part of the body is affected by the disease, etc.) areconsidered to be irrelevant or inappropriate. The important consequenceof this is that the Methodists might have been perfectly well aware of some38 See now Moog (1994) [<strong>and</strong> Tecusan (2004)].39 Incidentally, one might conclude from this that, other things being equal, for the reconstruction ofmainstream Methodist doctrine we are in a much better position with Caelius Aurelianus than withSoranus (contra Lloyd (1983) 185–6: ‘For our purposes the extant original Greek of the Gynaecologyis both more reliable <strong>and</strong> more interesting than the paraphrastic Latin versions of his Acute <strong>and</strong>Chronic Diseases that we have from Caelius Aurelianus’).40 Chron. 2.12.146. Cf.Sor.,Gyn. 1.4.41 This point has been made by Gourevitch (1991) 67–8 against Edelstein (1967b) 173–91. See alsoLloyd (1983) 183.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!