12.07.2015 Views

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

162 Aristotle <strong>and</strong> his schoolto use it as a starting point for a discussion on the instability (anōmalia)ofthe melancholic nature rather than for any other purpose. 79 In addition,the text explicitly states that the physiological balance which forms the basisof extraordinary achievements is uncertain <strong>and</strong> unstable. 80 These two factsunderline the exceptional nature of the melancholic peritton; they clearlyshow that this notion was apparently considered a negligible factor <strong>and</strong> assuch played no part in Aristotle’s theory of virtue, <strong>and</strong> as a philosophicallyinsignificant empirical phenomenon was only discussed in a text such asthe Problemata. 81The fact that the medical observations that are so typical of the Problemataare absent from Aristotle’s statements on melancholics <strong>and</strong> the factthat Aristotle only discusses the ‘manic’ or ‘passionate’ expressions of melancholy(Flashar (1962) 713) therefore do not, in my opinion, have any implicationfor the relationship between Aristotle <strong>and</strong> Pr. 30.1. The differencein objectives between these texts, <strong>and</strong> in particular Aristotle’s fundamentallylimited interest in medical issues in his works on natural science (<strong>and</strong>a fortiori those on ethics), seem largely to explain this lack of balance orat least make it underst<strong>and</strong>able. In Aristotle’s work, the number of passagesin which the ‘manic’ expressions of the melancholic nature are worthmentioning as illustrative examples (for instance contexts that mention itssensitivity to desires <strong>and</strong> passions) outnumber the passages that would besuitable for mentioning its ‘depressive’ manifestations. On a total of nineoccurrences, this might prove a sufficient explanation. In addition, it shouldbe noted that Aristotle fully takes into account the effects of cold that aretypical to melancholy, as is shown in Somn. vig. 457 a 31 (i.e. disregardingMag. mor. 1203 b 1, which is probably not written by Aristotle <strong>and</strong> thereforedoes not constitute proof).The most important reason for any irreconcilability between Aristotle’sview on melancholy <strong>and</strong> the theory presented in Pr. 30.1 has so far beengiven little attention by scholars. This reason would be that Aristotle denies79 This observation is very much in accordance with the fact that the structure of the text differs greatlyfrom the other Problemata. Similarly, it fits in well with the suggestion (see Flashar (1962) 711, 714;Flashar (1966) 61; Müri (1953) 21) that this chapter consists of an editorial combination of a typicalProblemata question <strong>and</strong> an excerpt of a treatise on melancholy, in which answering the questionposed at the start of the chapter was perhaps not the main objective of the author. For a differentexplanation for the structure of this chapter see section 7 below.80 Tellenbach (1961, 9) correctly states that these perittoi are characterised by an above-average instability.81 In this respect the peritton of melancholics can be compared to the phenomenon of eutuchia,discussed in Eth. Eud. 8.2 (see ch. 8 below), with divination in sleep as discussed in On Divination inSleep (see ch. 6 below) [<strong>and</strong> the peritton mentioned in Part. an. 4.10, 686 b 26]. Although Aristotleconsiders both to be results of experience, they play no part in his ethics <strong>and</strong> psychology, perhapsbecause of their uncontrollable nature <strong>and</strong> instability.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!