12.07.2015 Views

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

262 Aristotle <strong>and</strong> his schooldoctrine between works whose Aristotelian authorship is beyond dispute, oreven within one <strong>and</strong> the same work (see below), so the question is whetherthe divergences between ‘Hist. an. 10’ <strong>and</strong> Generation of Animals are suchthat they cannot conceivably be derived from Aristotle’s own mind.In this chapter, however, I will approach this question from a ratherdifferent angle by drawing attention to the special nature of ‘Hist. an. 10’.I will argue that the divergences of doctrine between ‘Hist. an. 10’ <strong>and</strong>other Aristotelian works need not exclusively be interpreted as evidence ofdifferent authorship, or indeed of a development in Aristotle’s thought, butmay be better appreciated when we relate them to differences in scientificstatus <strong>and</strong> methodology between these works. To put it briefly, ‘Hist. an.10’ is a ‘practical’, that is, medical work, unsystematic <strong>and</strong> limited in scope,intended to provide diagnostic clues as to the possible causes of failure toconceive, or in other words, pursuing knowledge that is useful for practicalapplication. 12 Thus it is very different in nature from a thoroughly theoretical,systematic, <strong>and</strong> comprehensive work such as Generation of Animals.From this perspective, it becomes underst<strong>and</strong>able that ‘Hist. an. 10’ mainlydiscusses additional factors that are supplementary to the account of Generationof Animals, <strong>and</strong> on the other h<strong>and</strong> does not mention a numberof factors which play such a crucial role in Generation of Animals. It alsoexplains the book’s anthropocentric approach, the fact that it deals almostexclusively with problems on the female side <strong>and</strong> why it so persistentlyconsiders aspects of failure to conceive in relation to whether they require,or allow of, ‘treatment’ ().The assumption that Aristotle wrote medical works at all (<strong>and</strong> that ‘Hist.an. 10’ was one of them) may need some elaboration. As is well known,Aristotle makes a clear distinction between practical <strong>and</strong> theoretical sciences13 <strong>and</strong> is well aware of its implications for the way in which a particulartopic is discussed within the context of one kind of science ratherthan the other 14 – such implications pertaining, among other things, to thedegree of exactitude with which the topic is to be discussed, the kind ofquestions to be asked <strong>and</strong> the amount of technical detail to be covered (agood example of such differences in treatment is the discussion of the soul<strong>and</strong> its various parts in the Ethics <strong>and</strong> in On the Soul ). As far as medicineis concerned, Aristotle expresses a similar view on the differences between12 The possibility that ‘Hist. an. 10’ is different in style <strong>and</strong> doctrine from other Aristotelian worksbecause it is practical in nature <strong>and</strong> addresses a wider readership is suggested by Gigon (1983) 503,but he does not elaborate on this, <strong>and</strong> he also seems to think that the work was revised <strong>and</strong> updatedby a later Peripatetic in the light of new evidence.13 See, e.g., Metaph. 1025 b 25; 993 b 21; Top. 145 a 16.14 See, e.g., Eth. Nic. 1094 b 1ff.; 1098 a 21ff.; 1102 a 5ff.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!