12.07.2015 Views

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Aristotle on sleep <strong>and</strong> dreams 171discussed. For although Aristotle, within the scope of these short treatises,covers an admirable amount of topics <strong>and</strong> aspects of the phenomenon ofdreaming with a sometimes striking degree of sophistication, it is at thesame time remarkable that some important aspects of dreaming are nottreated at all – aspects which are of interest not only to us, but also toAristotle’s contemporaries. Let me give two examples. (i) Aristotle doesnot appear to be interested in the contents of dreams, in their narrativestructure or in the mechanism responsible for the sequence of events <strong>and</strong>experiences that occur to the dreamer in a certain order. Nor does he payserious attention to the interpretation of dreams: he only makes some verygeneral remarks about this towards the end (464 b 9–16); he does notspecify the rules for a correct interpretation of dreams. Yet the meaning ofdreams was what the Greeks were most concerned with, <strong>and</strong> we know thatin Aristotle’s time there existed professional dream interpreters who usedhighly elaborated techniques to establish the meaning of dreams. 8 (ii) Afurther striking fact is that Aristotle hardly discusses the relation of dreamswith other mental processes during sleep, such as thinking <strong>and</strong> recollection.He has little to say on questions such as: can we think in sleep? can we solvemathematical problems in sleep? (a problem that attracted much attentionin later thought on dreams, e.g. in medieval Arabic dream theory). This lackof interest calls for an explanation, for not only does experience evidentlysuggest that these mental operations are possible in sleep, but there was alsoa powerful tradition in Greek thought, widespread in Aristotle’s time, thatsome mental operations, such as abstract thinking (nous), could functionbetter <strong>and</strong> more accurately in sleep than in the waking state, because theywere believed to be ‘set free’ in sleep from the restrictions posed by the soul’sincorporation in the body. Why does Aristotle not address this issue?Now, in response to this, one could argue that Aristotle was under noconstraint from earlier traditions to discuss these points, for early <strong>and</strong> classicalGreek thought tends to display rather ambivalent attitudes to thephenomenon of sleep, <strong>and</strong> in particular to whether we can exercise ourcognitive faculties in sleep. On the one h<strong>and</strong>, there was a str<strong>and</strong> in Greekthought, especially in some medical circles, in which sleep was definednegatively as the absence of a number of activities <strong>and</strong> abilities that arecharacteristic of the waking life, such as sense-perception, movement, consciousness<strong>and</strong> thinking. And as we shall see in a moment, Aristotle’s theoryof sleep shows strong similarities to this tradition. On the other h<strong>and</strong>, therewas also a str<strong>and</strong> in Greek thought, represented both in Orphic circles but8 See del Corno (1982).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!