12.07.2015 Views

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

Medicine and philosophy - Classical Homeopathy Online

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

214 Aristotle <strong>and</strong> his schoolpower to see resemblances, 25 at the basis ofrational underst<strong>and</strong>ing, which is characteristic of human cognition. Thusvariations that seem to be merely necessary concomitants of other, purposivebiological structures <strong>and</strong> processes – <strong>and</strong> thus seem to be ‘natural’ only in the mechanical sense – can sometimes be accountedfor indirectly as being ‘natural’ in a teleological sense as well.This coexistence of two approaches need not be problematic: Aristotleis very much aware of the difference between teleological <strong>and</strong> mechanicalexplanations <strong>and</strong> is convinced of their being, to a very large extent,complementary. One might also say that the principle of ‘naturalness’ is applied by Aristotle at different levels: he does not shrinkfrom saying that even within the category of things happening ‘contrary tonature’ , such as the occurrence of deviations, deformations<strong>and</strong> monstrosities, there is such a thing as ‘the natural’ ; 26deviations from the natural procedure can nevertheless display regularity,such as, again, the melancholics, who are said to be naturally abnormal. 27The difficulty that remains, however, is how explanations offered for thesevariations <strong>and</strong> deviations are to be related to explanations offered for thenormal procedure. This difficulty is especially urgent with variations inintellectual capacities; for these are explained with a reference to differencesin bodily conditions of the individuals concerned, which raises the questionof what the bodily conditions for a ‘normal’ operating of the intellect are<strong>and</strong> how this is to be related to Aristotle’s ‘normative’ view of thinkingas an incorporeal process: is the influence of these bodily conditions indeviations to be regarded as ‘interference’ in a process which normally hasno physical aspect whatsoever, or is there also such a thing as a ‘normal’ or‘healthy’ bodily state which acts as a physical substrate to thinking?A related difficulty presents itself in the ethical domain. On the oneh<strong>and</strong>, Aristotle tries to connect his views on what is best for man withwhat he believes to be man’s natural activity . 28 On the otherh<strong>and</strong>, he also notoriously tries to provide a biological foundation for hisbelief that not all human beings are equally capable of realising the moral<strong>and</strong> intellectual virtues, 29 which is at the basis of his views on politicalorganisation (e.g. his views on the naturalness of the state, slavery, <strong>and</strong>25 On this principle see Lambert (1966) <strong>and</strong> van der Eijk (1994) 326 <strong>and</strong> 333.26 Gen. an. 770 b 10ff. 27 Eth. Nic. 1154 b 11; Pr. 954 b 8ff.; 955 a 40.28 See Eth. Nic. 1097 b 25ff.29 See the condition of natural ability in Eth. Nic. 1099 b 17ff.: ‘In this way, happiness is also common tomany; for it is possible for it to be available through some sort of learning <strong>and</strong> practising to all thosewho are not disabled in respect of virtue’ ( [sc. ] ).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!