05.12.2012 Views

Beowulf - Institutionen för arkeologi och antik historia

Beowulf - Institutionen för arkeologi och antik historia

Beowulf - Institutionen för arkeologi och antik historia

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

order to survive and develop, but at the same time it is also an example of a suitable<br />

context: <strong>Beowulf</strong> visiting the Danish court in his father’s company. There is a similar<br />

example in the meeting between the Latin-loving Lupus and the amiable young<br />

Venantius on the occasion of the wedding between Sigibert and Brunhild. In that<br />

example too the hall and its community constitute a suitable context which makes it<br />

possible to form a relationship based upon unconditional goodness.<br />

<strong>Beowulf</strong>’s goodness, on the other hand, although based on the unconditional, is<br />

inspired by the idea of honouring a contract set up between the hero, in his capacity<br />

as a retainer or drengR, and the king. This social practice is neither a loan from the<br />

classical tradition of virtue nor a continuation from the Early Germanic tradition of<br />

loyalty as a duty to an elected chieftain or king. There are obviously possible connections,<br />

but the contract represents something new, namely a practical way of selecting<br />

the individual: a way of pointing him out as an aristocrat and eventually a<br />

responsible leader and, moreover, a way of securing for him the wealth which is<br />

necessary to live a good life, but not sufficient to create it.<br />

This means that when looking for the roots of the Late Iron Age concept of being<br />

good we may expect remote connections with an unspecified Aristotelian and Greek<br />

as well as with an Early Germanic tradition, but also a strong affinity with a new<br />

Germanic tradition. We can therefore conclude that concepts like goodness, virtue<br />

or honour have very deep roots, but also that goodness in its Late Iron Age version<br />

exploits and transforms older traditions for obvious power-political reasons and as<br />

part of the ongoing process of social stratification<br />

The good designates the individual and those of his actions that, in the long run,<br />

maintain the civilised or, indeed, the good society. The concept is complex, it can<br />

create conflicts and it is partly reserved for the individuals of the upper strata of<br />

society. Due to its character of a contract which must be honoured, even good people<br />

in the upper classes may find themselves in troublesome conflicts when trying to<br />

be good. Since the concept involves areas of general conflict in a society, the negation<br />

of being good is not always to be bad or evil—we may just be more or less<br />

lacking in goodness.<br />

The glimpses we have received of the lower classes, i.e., Sabas, have showed us<br />

that here people may be considered evil or monstrous by the upper classes, while<br />

they are themselves prepared to defend their goodness, and to define the good<br />

members of the upper classes as utterly evil and monstrous. Sabas’ goodness is a<br />

matter of a world-rejecting disposition as well as of actions. It is, moreover, very<br />

Christian. Sabas’ attitude, or rather hate, towards the representatives of the nobility,<br />

whose behaviour is modelled on that of <strong>Beowulf</strong>, convinces us of the possible social<br />

conflict behind the notion of the good. But even from an aristocratic point of view not<br />

everybody in the upper classes is good. This implies that doing the good is a universally<br />

accepted means of social selection.<br />

150

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!