15.08.2016 Views

Buddhist Romanticism

BuddhistRomanticism151003

BuddhistRomanticism151003

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

coherence of a character’s motivations as might be presented in a novel:<br />

You can understand where the character is coming from, and what he or<br />

she is trying to achieve by a particular action, even if the character can’t cite<br />

logical first principles to justify that action. On the other hand, the<br />

coherence of these doctrines of freedom resembles the coherence in the<br />

author’s attitude when putting energy into the act of artistic creation: As<br />

Schlegel said, a poet needs to believe in the power of the human spirit to<br />

impress its laws on all things. Not to believe in that power would, for an<br />

author, be debilitating.<br />

These doctrines on the meaning of freedom, whatever their validity as<br />

guidelines for aspiring artists, were totally inadequate as guidelines for<br />

implementing a social program. That’s because, despite their differing<br />

emphases, they shared one point in common: They teach freedom without<br />

accountability. There is no discussion of the consequences of one’s actions,<br />

or of how to resolve conflicts arising when one person’s exercise of his or<br />

her freedom gets in the way of someone else’s. A social philosophy that<br />

offers no means by which individuals would be held accountable for their<br />

actions and no means for adjudicating conflicts is no social philosophy at<br />

all. It’s a recipe for chaos.<br />

The Romantics, of course, insisted that if all people were to exercise their<br />

freedom from a direct intuition of the infinite organic unity of the cosmos,<br />

there would be no abuse of freedom and no conflicts. A sense of fellowfeeling<br />

would inspire everyone to treat one another with tenderness and<br />

compassion. But the disturbing feature of their views on freedom is not<br />

simply that issues of responsibility are not mentioned. The whole idea of<br />

responsibility and accountability becomes impossible.<br />

It might be argued that Novalis, Schlegel, and Hölderlin—with their<br />

ironic, magical, novelistic approach to freedom and truth—were simply<br />

embodying Schiller’s doctrine of the play drive: People find freedom and<br />

learn about morality through play. To take an ironic stance toward the<br />

world, or to look for the magical in the commonplace, is to exercise one’s<br />

freedom to play. From play, comes morality. But this Romantic version of<br />

Schiller’s idea, when regarded from Schiller’s overall viewpoint, is missing<br />

an important step. The play drive, in his eyes, had to be trained to lead to a<br />

sense of moral responsibility: the realization that, for play to be a long-term<br />

activity, one had to act responsibly, in line with rules of reason, and that<br />

one’s feelings had to be trained to love those rules. Otherwise, the game of<br />

147

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!