15.08.2016 Views

Buddhist Romanticism

BuddhistRomanticism151003

BuddhistRomanticism151003

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Some typical answers were these:<br />

• The world is just as we perceive it, and it can be understood by working down<br />

to first principles—about what things are in their essence, both in the world and in<br />

the mind—and then deriving our experience from those principles.<br />

• The world exists only in the mind, which is the only essential substance there<br />

is.<br />

• There is no way that we can know the essences of things, for all we know are<br />

representations derived through the senses. We can’t even know if causality is<br />

really at work behind our sense data, because causality can never be seen in action.<br />

Even our self is unknowable. It’s simply an assumption that lies outside the range<br />

of our senses.<br />

Kant gained his reputation as a major philosopher because of the novel<br />

and provocative way he addressed these questions. Instead of focusing on a<br />

quest to confirm or deny essences outside or inside, he looked at the way<br />

consciousness interacted with the input of the senses, showing that the<br />

basic raw material of knowledge is composed not of sense data, but of<br />

judgments about sense data. In other words, what we perceive directly is<br />

not things-in-themselves in the world outside or the self inside, but the<br />

workings of reason in shaping experience in the middle ground. We make<br />

our experience, and—as Kant often said—we know best, not what is, but<br />

what we make.<br />

However, this fact does not prevent us from coming to objective<br />

conclusions about our place in the world, for if we examine, through<br />

introspection, the workings of reason in action, we can penetrate beyond<br />

the subjective content of our experiences to their objective structure or form,<br />

which has to be the same for all conscious, rational beings. In other words,<br />

we learn objective facts about the world of experience by observing the<br />

ways our reason has to shape it. Kant called this approach critical, in that it<br />

took a critical view of the powers and limitations of reason, and<br />

transcendental, in that it sought to discover necessary, objective forms of<br />

conscious activity that transcended the purely subjective level; i.e., all<br />

subjective experience had to presuppose and follow these forms. (Kant’s<br />

meaning of the term transcendental here differs from the meanings that other<br />

thinkers will be using throughout this book, so take note of how these<br />

meanings change.)<br />

One of the consequences of this critical, transcendental approach is that<br />

Kant developed a novel criterion for truth. Because things-in-themselves<br />

92

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!