09.03.2014 Aufrufe

Heft - Institut für Theorie ith

Heft - Institut für Theorie ith

Heft - Institut für Theorie ith

MEHR ANZEIGEN
WENIGER ANZEIGEN

Erfolgreiche ePaper selbst erstellen

Machen Sie aus Ihren PDF Publikationen ein blätterbares Flipbook mit unserer einzigartigen Google optimierten e-Paper Software.

On the first pages of his last big book<br />

Logiques des mondes Alain Badiou has<br />

proposed the term “democratic materialism”<br />

to name the prevailing and spontaneous<br />

set of assumptions which form<br />

the contemporary doxa. According to<br />

him, this democratic materialism can<br />

be summarized w<strong>ith</strong> one “ontological”<br />

statement: “There are only bodies and<br />

languages.” / “Il n’y que des corps et des<br />

langages.” 17 There is the firm being of<br />

bodies, their proliferation, their striving<br />

for pleasures and enjoyment, the<br />

increase, growth and expansion of life;<br />

and there is the multiplicity of languages,<br />

the democracy of their plurality and<br />

proliferation, multiculturalism, minoritarian<br />

practices, all of them entitled to<br />

recognition. Democratic materialism is<br />

the spontaneous idealism of our times<br />

– nobody believes any longer in the salvation<br />

of the immortal soul, we firmly<br />

believe in bodies and languages. Ba -<br />

diou’s addition to this axiom is simple:<br />

“There are only bodies and languages,<br />

but apart from that there are truths.” /<br />

“Il n’y a que des corps et des langages,<br />

sinon qu’il y a des vérités.” 18 There are<br />

truths which are of a di≠erent order than<br />

bodies and languages, they engage subjectivity<br />

and raise a claim to universality,<br />

but they do not exist on some separate<br />

location somewhere else. For our<br />

particular purpose we could say that<br />

they emerge precisely w<strong>ith</strong> that excess<br />

at the interface of bodies and languages,<br />

something that psychoanalysis<br />

brings together under the names of the<br />

unconscious and of sexuality. They<br />

emerge at the intersection which prevents<br />

the neutral coexistence of bodies<br />

and languages, in a subtraction from<br />

the regime of bodies and languages,<br />

epitomized by the Other. Bodies and<br />

signs can be counted, but the Other<br />

makes for a two which is uncountable.<br />

The axiom of democratic materialism<br />

has a corollary: there are only bodies<br />

and languages, but there is no Other.<br />

The promotion of their expansion and<br />

proliferation precludes the Other. And<br />

this is where our adage that the Other<br />

lacks takes precisely the opposite direction:<br />

it does not mean that, since it<br />

lacks, we are only stuck w<strong>ith</strong> bodies and<br />

languages, happily or unhappily stuck,<br />

it means that the very existence of bodies<br />

and languages has to be put into<br />

question. It is the two of the Other that<br />

undermines their multiplicity and proliferation.<br />

The two which is ne<strong>ith</strong>er one<br />

nor multiple provides a precarious hold<br />

on truth.<br />

The question of the two has a pre-Socratic<br />

air to it, it aims straight at the<br />

first principles, it strives to pinpoint the<br />

minimal conditions of thought, starting<br />

w<strong>ith</strong> one and two. So let me finish<br />

w<strong>ith</strong> the pre-Socratics and the minimal,<br />

and let me raise the final issue of<br />

materialism (as opposed to its democratic<br />

variety). The first appearance of<br />

materialism in the history of philosophy<br />

is linked to the atomists, and most notably<br />

to the figure of Democritus. What is<br />

atomism, if not a radical attempt to submit<br />

bodies, and the whole matter, to<br />

count. Matter can be counted, and the<br />

atoms are its indivisible elements, the<br />

hard particles that enable counting. Or<br />

so it would seem. The atom would thus<br />

be the pure minimal element of matter<br />

that cannot be reduced any further, and<br />

this is what enables them to be counted<br />

for one. Yet, this is not their su∞cient<br />

definition, as Georg Wilhelm Friedrich<br />

Hegel was quick to point out. The particles<br />

require the empty space, the void<br />

where they move and which surrounds<br />

them, and if we single them out as<br />

units, we have to include the void as<br />

“the other half” of their firm being.<br />

“The atomistic principle, w<strong>ith</strong> these first<br />

thinkers, did not remain in exteriority,<br />

but apart from its abstraction contained<br />

a speculative determination, that the<br />

void was recognized as the source of<br />

movement. This implies a completely<br />

di≠erent relation between atoms and<br />

the void than the mere one-beside-theother<br />

[in German: ‘Nebeneinander,’ M.<br />

D.] and mutual indi≠erence of the two.<br />

[…] The view that the cause of movement<br />

lies in the void contains that deeper<br />

thought that the cause of becoming pertains<br />

to the negative.” 19<br />

17 - Alain Badiou, Logiques des<br />

mondes, Paris 2006, p. 9.<br />

18 - Ibid., p. 12.<br />

19 - Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,<br />

Wissenschaft der Logik, Eva<br />

Moldenhauer / Karl Markus<br />

Michel (red.), Werke, vol. 6–7,<br />

Frankfurt a. M. 1979, vol. 6,<br />

pp. 185–186.<br />

20 - Lacan, The Four Fundamental<br />

Concepts (note 15), pp. 63–64.<br />

21 - Hermann Diels, Die Fragmente<br />

der Vorsokratiker, 3 vol., Walther<br />

Kranz (ed.), Berlin 1934, vol. 2,<br />

p. 174, fragm. 156.<br />

So the minimal element of matter is not<br />

the atom as the indivisible particle, but<br />

a double entity composed of the particle<br />

and the void, of being and nothing;<br />

of “marque” and “manque.” The most<br />

palpably material seems to behave like<br />

a signifying structure. When matter is<br />

submitted to count one hits upon the<br />

signifier and its dyad. One did not have<br />

to wait for Saussure. However far we<br />

divide, we always get to a split entity,<br />

split into itself and its absence. Yet, the<br />

Hegelian view is not the whole story, for<br />

in this way we would precisely get to the<br />

one of (numerical) count, thus perhaps<br />

catch and spell out the secret of counting<br />

at the dawn of philosophy, but we would<br />

not get to the figure of the (uncountable)<br />

two. But this figure is there in Democritus,<br />

in the very way he conceives the<br />

atom, and Lacan singled it out:<br />

“[…] tuché brings us back to the same<br />

point at which pre-Socratic philosophy<br />

sought to motivate the world itself.<br />

It required a clinamen, an inclination,<br />

at some point. When Democritus<br />

tried to designate it, presenting himself<br />

as already the adversary of a pure function<br />

of negativity in order to introduce<br />

thought into it, he says, It is not the<br />

μηδέν [non-being, M. D.] that is essential<br />

[…] but a δέν, which, in Greek, is a<br />

coined word. He did not say ἕν [one, M.<br />

D.], let alone ὄν [being, M. D.]. What,<br />

then, did he say? He said, answering the<br />

question I asked today, that of idealism,<br />

Nothing, perhaps? – not perhaps nothing,<br />

but not nothing.” 20<br />

Lacan takes up the coinage of a new<br />

Greek word by Democritus, δέν, a strange<br />

entity which escapes the alternative<br />

between being and nothing: it is not a<br />

being but ne<strong>ith</strong>er is it a nothing, it gives<br />

an existence to negativity, yet not by<br />

being something that one could identify<br />

or lay one’s hands on or count as one.<br />

The word stems from the negation of<br />

ἕν, one, and this condenses our problem.<br />

ἕν can be negated in Greek in two<br />

ways, e<strong>ith</strong>er as ὀυδέν (objective negation)<br />

or as μηδέν (subjective negation),<br />

and they would both mean “nothing”<br />

(although w<strong>ith</strong> a di≠erent shading),<br />

“not one” (or “not even one”). δέν, which<br />

is an improper word formation, means<br />

like “less than one, but still not nothing.”<br />

It is a tricky word that caused a lot<br />

of headache to classical philologists –<br />

they have amply commented on this<br />

famous fragment 156. Hermann Diels<br />

translates this curious word by “das<br />

Ichts” (“Das Nichts existiert ebenso sehr<br />

als das Ichts” 21 – and most curiously,<br />

the German neologism “das Ichts” was<br />

90

Hurra! Ihre Datei wurde hochgeladen und ist bereit für die Veröffentlichung.

Erfolgreich gespeichert!

Leider ist etwas schief gelaufen!