09.03.2014 Aufrufe

Heft - Institut für Theorie ith

Heft - Institut für Theorie ith

Heft - Institut für Theorie ith

MEHR ANZEIGEN
WENIGER ANZEIGEN

Erfolgreiche ePaper selbst erstellen

Machen Sie aus Ihren PDF Publikationen ein blätterbares Flipbook mit unserer einzigartigen Google optimierten e-Paper Software.

31 N°- 14/15<br />

The Figure of Two<br />

Alenka Zupančič<br />

The<br />

Double<br />

and Its<br />

Relationship<br />

to the<br />

Real<br />

There is a very singular and undoubtedly<br />

very fascinating figure of the Two,<br />

which has – among di≠erent figures of<br />

the Two – a rather distinguished status,<br />

due to the important role it has played<br />

in art, especially in literature. This is the<br />

figure of the double and, more broadly<br />

speaking, of redoubling. In the following<br />

discussion of this figure I will not<br />

speak so much about its history and its<br />

articulations in literature, but will rather<br />

focus on its fundamental structure<br />

and its philosophical implications. In<br />

order to do this, I will engage in a dialog<br />

w<strong>ith</strong> an author who has dedicated most<br />

of his philosophical work to this topic,<br />

albeit from a very specific critical perspective.<br />

The author is Clément Rosset,<br />

a very interesting figure of contemporary<br />

French philosophy, although (and<br />

strangely) not so well known and translated<br />

outside France. I will be arguing<br />

as much w<strong>ith</strong> Rosset as against him; for,<br />

several irreconcilable di≠erences notw<strong>ith</strong>standing,<br />

Rosset develops many<br />

things which, in my conceptual space<br />

(strongly curbed by the Lacanian theory),<br />

resonate in a surprising way which<br />

can be very productive to engage w<strong>ith</strong>.<br />

To begin w<strong>ith</strong> we could say that<br />

the double is not exactly a one, yet it also<br />

does not constitute a two in the ordinary<br />

sense of the term. It seems to be ne<strong>ith</strong>er one, nor two.<br />

Two identical bottles of beer are not doubles, as far as there is<br />

place for both in the reality of, say, our refrigerator. And if we<br />

think of it, the notion of a double presupposes not so much<br />

the sameness of appearance or manifestation, as the sameness<br />

of the time and place. The figure of the double involves<br />

a duality or a two that compete for the same time and place<br />

or simply for the same reality as structured by time and<br />

space (for in reality, there is never place / time for both). It<br />

seems that – to take the example of the entities called people<br />

– we do not simply inhabit a certain place and move in space,<br />

but also, and on a more fundamental level, carry our place<br />

w<strong>ith</strong> us wherever we go. Even if we appear somewhere as<br />

completely out of place, or at an utterly wrong time, we still<br />

seem to be “ourselves” ontologically speaking – we are out of<br />

place in relation to some symbolic configuration, but it<br />

seems that we can never be out of place in the real; in the real<br />

we are always at our place (and time), which is finally our<br />

(only) real. At this level, we are e<strong>ith</strong>er at our place, or else we<br />

are not at all (we have no being). The double is precisely<br />

what is threatening at this very ontological level, for it introduces<br />

an “impossible” split into the very homogeneity of this<br />

real, that is into the very homogeneity of being and its “taking<br />

place.” We can get a good grip of what this means in the<br />

following aphorism by Stanislaw Jerzy Lec, a famous Polish<br />

aphorist: “Who knows what Columbus might have discovered<br />

had America not blocked his way!” This suggestion of a<br />

double is a very ingenious one, for it suggests that reality<br />

itself is the double which has most literally usurped (blocked)<br />

the place of something else.<br />

So, if the figure of the double implies something more<br />

than one, it also implies something less than two: it is not about<br />

two constituted ontological entities, but rather something<br />

that induces a doubt into the (original) one as<br />

ontological entity. Rosset is very right in pointing<br />

out this characteristic of the double. He reverses<br />

the standard diagnosis of Otto Rank who linked<br />

the anxiety in the face of a double to our primordial<br />

fear of death. We usually consider the reality<br />

of the double to be “better” than ours – and in this<br />

sense it can indeed seem that the double represents<br />

an immortal instance in relation to the subject<br />

(which is Rank’s thesis). However, the real<br />

source of our anxiety is not simply our future<br />

death, but above all our (present) non-reality and<br />

non-existence. It would not be so hard to die if we<br />

knew for sure that we have at least lived; but it is<br />

precisely this life, as perishable as it is, that the<br />

subject starts to doubt in the cases of “split personality”<br />

or appearing of a double. In the ill-fated<br />

couple in which I am united w<strong>ith</strong> a phantom other,<br />

the real is not on my side, but rather on the side<br />

of the phantom: it is not the other that redoubles<br />

me, it is rather that I am the other’s double. 1 In<br />

short, when my double appears, my present existence<br />

(my being as such) appears as utmost uncertain.<br />

Hence, and to repeat: the figure of the double<br />

it is not about two constituted ontological entities,<br />

but rather something that induces a doubt in the<br />

(original) one as ontological entity.<br />

Let this su∞ce as introduction, and let us<br />

now first look more closely at Rosset and his arguments.<br />

Rosset dedicated most of his philosophical<br />

work to the theme best encapsulated in the title of<br />

his central book Le réel et son double. In it, he<br />

develops his arguments around the following fundamental<br />

observation: the real always tends to<br />

strike us as impossible to tolerate in some way –<br />

too cruel and disagreeable, or else too simple and<br />

idiotic. In our general relationship to the real he<br />

thus recognizes an attitude that betrays both anxiety<br />

and contempt (disregard): anxiety as to the<br />

fact that the real is really only just what it is, and<br />

the coextensive contempt for the real in its “idiotic”<br />

simplicity and plainness. Hence a whole<br />

number of strategies that aim at circumventing<br />

the real, and replacing it w<strong>ith</strong> something else<br />

which we then declare to be the actual, true real.<br />

On the basis of numerous examples Rosset develops<br />

a lucid and often amusing analysis of these<br />

strategies, pointing at their common denominator,<br />

which is the redoubling, or duplication of the<br />

real, and the enthronement of its double.<br />

First of all I would like to suggest that the<br />

notion of the real and its redoubling that he presents<br />

via di≠erent examples and their di≠erent<br />

1 - See Clément Rosset, Le réel<br />

et son double, Paris 1984, p. 91.<br />

2 - This structure has been<br />

analyzed exemplarily by Octave<br />

Mannoni in his article “Je sais<br />

bien mais quand même,” in:<br />

Clefs pour l'Imaginaire ou l'Autre<br />

scène, Paris 1969, pp. 9–33.<br />

It is therefore quite curious that<br />

there is no reference to him in<br />

Rosset’s book.<br />

3 - All translations from French in<br />

this essay A. Z., Rosset, Le réel<br />

(note 1), pp. 21f.<br />

94

Hurra! Ihre Datei wurde hochgeladen und ist bereit für die Veröffentlichung.

Erfolgreich gespeichert!

Leider ist etwas schief gelaufen!