09.03.2014 Aufrufe

Heft - Institut für Theorie ith

Heft - Institut für Theorie ith

Heft - Institut für Theorie ith

MEHR ANZEIGEN
WENIGER ANZEIGEN

Sie wollen auch ein ePaper? Erhöhen Sie die Reichweite Ihrer Titel.

YUMPU macht aus Druck-PDFs automatisch weboptimierte ePaper, die Google liebt.

Mladen<br />

Dollar<br />

91<br />

One<br />

Splits<br />

into<br />

Two<br />

introduced already by Meister Eckhart).<br />

Barbara Cassin, a formidable French<br />

scholar, proposes a French translation<br />

for δέν, which is “ien” – not “rien,” nothing,<br />

but “ien,” precisely “not nothing,” as<br />

Lacan says; 22 or alternatively “iun,” not<br />

one. The English translation by W. I.<br />

Matson proposes the “hing” as opposed<br />

to the thing: “Hing is no more real than<br />

nothing” or “Hing exists no more than<br />

nothing.” 23 So what is this entity, δέν?<br />

Not something, not nothing, not being,<br />

not one, not positively existing, not<br />

absent, not countable – and thus providing<br />

the minimal figure of the two.<br />

This is perhaps the closest that philosophy,<br />

at its dawn, would ever come to<br />

what Lacan, at the other end, would<br />

name “objet a,” the object a, and which<br />

he saw as his crucial contribution to<br />

psychoanalysis, his key theoretical<br />

invention. I can only hint that Lacan<br />

speaks about this at the end of the session<br />

on repetition, where he raises the<br />

question of τύχη and ἀυτόματον, and<br />

he brings together the Aristotelian τύχη<br />

w<strong>ith</strong> the δέν of Democritus, this notnothing,<br />

as one of the clues of repetition.<br />

One can simply and rather summarily<br />

say that δέν is also what is at<br />

stake in repetition, an entity which is<br />

being repeated w<strong>ith</strong>out having a proper<br />

consistency or identity, a cause of the<br />

derailment of causality, but which cannot<br />

be given a separate ontological stature,<br />

an entity inhabiting a crack, not a<br />

positive being but not a nothing.<br />

22 - See Barbara Cassin, “Pour une<br />

sécheresse logique,” in: Yannick<br />

Haenel / François Meyronnis<br />

(ed.), Ligne de risqué, 1997–2005,<br />

Paris 2005, p. 46. Now amply<br />

and magisterially in Alain<br />

Badiou / Barbara Cassin, Il n’y<br />

pas de rapport sexuel, Paris 2010,<br />

pp. 60–94.<br />

23 - W. I. Matson, “Democritus,<br />

Fragment 156,” in: The Classical<br />

Quarterly, 13, 1963, pp. 26–29.<br />

24 - “[Democritus] was no more<br />

materialist than anyone who has<br />

some sense, for instance me or<br />

Marx,” Jacques Lacan, “L’Étour-<br />

dit,” in: Autres écrits, Paris 2001,<br />

p. 494.<br />

25 - He proposes two points of depar -<br />

ture: “‘Naught is more real …’<br />

and the ‘Ubi nihil vales …’, both<br />

already in Murphy and ne<strong>ith</strong>er<br />

very rational,” Samuel Beckett,<br />

Disjecta, New York 1984, p. 113.<br />

The second one, ubi nihil vales<br />

ibi nihi velis stems from the 17th<br />

century Dutch occasionalist<br />

Arnold Geulincx.<br />

Lacan speaks of clinamen, a deviation,<br />

an inclination, which has already taken<br />

place w<strong>ith</strong> Democritus’ invention of<br />

δέν, a clinamen from the grand ontological<br />

tradition which was then being<br />

instituted, a deviation precisely from ἕν<br />

και πᾶν, clinamen from the One. Clinamen<br />

was the word used by Democritus’<br />

follower Epicurus, in a further development,<br />

the deviation of atoms which<br />

stands at the origin of the universe. Let<br />

me just recall in passing that the young<br />

Karl Marx in 1841 dedicated his doctoral<br />

dissertation in philosophy to the<br />

subject of The Di≠erence between the<br />

Philosophy of Nature of Democritus<br />

and Epicurus (Di≠erenz der demokritischen<br />

und epikureischen Naturphilosophie),<br />

where he insisted at<br />

length on the question of clinamen.<br />

This has hardly ever been brought in<br />

conceptual connection w<strong>ith</strong> his later<br />

philosophical path, but one could perhaps<br />

see in it something like a parable:<br />

a clinamen, a glitch, which lies at the<br />

beginning of the post-Hegelian era, a<br />

slight inclination, a slip, a departure<br />

from the horizon of the great philosophical<br />

tradition, from a grand narrative<br />

stretching from Parmenides to<br />

Hegel, a δέν opening another era after<br />

the end of philosophy. There is the sort<br />

of history of materialism yet to be<br />

written – from Democritus and Epicurus<br />

to Marx and Lacan 24 , and to Samuel<br />

Beckett.<br />

I will leave the last word to Beckett.<br />

When pressed about the philosophical<br />

interpretation of his work he said in a<br />

letter in 1967: “If I were in the unenviable<br />

position of having to study my<br />

work, my point of departure would be<br />

the ‘Naught is more real …’ 25 So Beckett<br />

himself proposed the Democritus fragment<br />

156 as the clue (one of the two<br />

clues) to his entire work. He used it<br />

already in Murphy (1938), his early<br />

novel, and then again in Malone Dies<br />

(1951), but more emphatically, δέν as<br />

“not nothing” is precisely the “unnullable<br />

least” that Beckett singled out in<br />

one of his last works, Worstward Ho!<br />

(1981). It can be seen as the name of<br />

what is at stake in Beckett’s relentless<br />

endeavor of reduction and perseverance,<br />

and the “unnullable least” is perhaps<br />

a very good name to think the figure<br />

of the two which resists the One<br />

and defies counting.

Hurra! Ihre Datei wurde hochgeladen und ist bereit für die Veröffentlichung.

Erfolgreich gespeichert!

Leider ist etwas schief gelaufen!