09.03.2014 Aufrufe

Heft - Institut für Theorie ith

Heft - Institut für Theorie ith

Heft - Institut für Theorie ith

MEHR ANZEIGEN
WENIGER ANZEIGEN

Erfolgreiche ePaper selbst erstellen

Machen Sie aus Ihren PDF Publikationen ein blätterbares Flipbook mit unserer einzigartigen Google optimierten e-Paper Software.

Alenka<br />

Zupančič<br />

95<br />

The Double<br />

and Its<br />

Relationship<br />

to the Real<br />

modalities is not as uniform as Rosset pretends,<br />

but involves in fact two di≠erent notions. One<br />

implies a real that roughly corresponds to reality<br />

w<strong>ith</strong> all its di∞culties and inconveniences, and in<br />

relationship to which we have the habit of practicing<br />

a whole lot of “illusions” – to borrow Rosset’s<br />

own term. This notion of illusion is very specific,<br />

and it refers ne<strong>ith</strong>er to an erroneous perception,<br />

nor to denial. It rather corresponds to the following<br />

configuration: we (correctly) perceive a thing<br />

and do not deny this perception, yet we refuse the<br />

consequences that should normally follow from it.<br />

Rosset’s funniest example here is a comic play by<br />

George Courteline Boubouroche (1893). In this<br />

play Boubouroche learns at some point (a hint<br />

from a friendly neighbor) that his lover Adèle is<br />

regularly cheating on him w<strong>ith</strong> a young lover, in<br />

the very apartment he put her in. So he shows up<br />

there by surprise and finds the lover in the closet.<br />

But Adèle manages to convince him very quickly<br />

that in spite of what he sees, she is guilty of nothing,<br />

that it is Boubouroche himself who is guilty of<br />

unspeakable vulgarity for busting on her like this,<br />

and that he is the one who has to apologize and<br />

ask for forgiveness. Which is what he does, furious<br />

w<strong>ith</strong> the neighbor who “misinformed” him.<br />

According to Rosset, Boubouroche’s reasoning<br />

can be summed up as follows: “There is a lover in<br />

Adèle’s closet (he never denies seeing this) – therefore<br />

Adèle is innocent and I am not a cuckold.” At<br />

stake in this notion of illusion is thus the following<br />

configuration: It is not that I do not want to see,<br />

and I do not deny the real that I see. But this is as<br />

far as I am prepared to go. I saw, I admitted, but<br />

do not ask any more from me. In all the rest I<br />

maintain my previous position. I go on as before,<br />

as if I saw nothing. One should point out that Rosset’s<br />

description here corresponds point by point<br />

to what psychoanalysis conceptualized w<strong>ith</strong> the<br />

notion of “(fetishist) disavowal” (“Verleugnung”),<br />

and which has precisely the structure of “I know<br />

very well (that this is how things stand), but nevertheless<br />

(I continue to behave as if it was not<br />

so).” 2 And, everything considered, the concept of<br />

disavowal might come closer to the mark of this<br />

configuration than the notion of redoubling.<br />

There is yet another notion of the real and<br />

its redoubling at work in a series of Rosset’s central<br />

examples, which, in my view, cannot be utterly<br />

reduced to this same logic of illusionist duplication<br />

/ disavowal. They have an even more farreaching<br />

and interesting structure, and they<br />

deserve separate attention. These are examples of<br />

the oracular, prophetic literature, and this is Rosset’s<br />

crucial and masterful observation in respect<br />

to them:<br />

“Oracles have a general and at the same time paradoxical<br />

characteristic that they come true and that<br />

they surprise w<strong>ith</strong> this very coming true. The oracle<br />

does us the favor of announcing the event in advance:<br />

so that the one for whom this event is destined<br />

has the leisure to prepare for it, and eventually to try<br />

to ward it o≠. The event is fulfilled such as it had been<br />

predicted (or announced by a dream, or some other<br />

sort of premonitory manifestation), and yet this fulfillment has a<br />

curious fortune of disappointing the expectation at the very<br />

moment when the latter would have to see itself as utterly fulfilled.<br />

A is announced, A happens, and we are lost, at least to some<br />

extent. Between the event such as it has been announced, and the<br />

event such as it was fulfilled, there is a kind of subtle di≠erence<br />

that su∞ces to baffle the very person who has been expecting precisely<br />

that what he is witnessing. He recognizes it all right, but he<br />

no longer recognizes himself in it. Yet nothing happened but the<br />

announced event. But the latter is inexplicably other.” 3<br />

Rosset supports this observation w<strong>ith</strong> numerous examples.<br />

There is, for instance, an old Arab tale that has seen many<br />

di≠erent versions, among which Somerset Maugham’s The<br />

Appointment in Samarra. But the most famous of these stories<br />

is of course Oedipus the King. And if we think of it, it is<br />

indeed very true that although what eventually takes place in<br />

this tragedy corresponds exactly to what has been predicted<br />

(that Oedipus would kill his father and marry his mother),<br />

we – together w<strong>ith</strong> Oedipus – cannot help but to be very<br />

much at a loss when it happens, or rather, when this turns<br />

out to be what actually happened. Rosset places this “subtle<br />

di≠erence that su∞ces to baffle the very person who has<br />

been expecting precisely that what he is witnessing” at the<br />

core of what he recognizes as splitting or duplication of the<br />

real at work – in a quasi-general way – in our attitude toward<br />

the world; or simply toward the real: we cannot put up w<strong>ith</strong><br />

the real in its idiotic simplicity and univocity, we simply cannot<br />

stand it that the real is only what it is, and has no other<br />

meaning or dimension.<br />

The example of a fulfilled prophecy elucidates this general<br />

propensity to duplication by presenting its other side: it<br />

confronts us w<strong>ith</strong> an unwelcome (and surprising) coincidence<br />

at a point where our “normal” existence would be<br />

more than satisfied w<strong>ith</strong> a split or non-coincidence between<br />

two versions (or two meanings) of the real. We thus tend to<br />

put the real aside and to install a double in its place – a double<br />

that has the advantage of suiting us better. However –<br />

here I am still following Rosset –, as it is clear from the stories<br />

that treat the theme of the double (oracular stories or,<br />

even more directly, stories about doubles), there is no possible<br />

double of the real, the latter always wins in its singularity,<br />

eliminating the other person or version of the events. Any<br />

kind of a double of the real is impossible, since the real is by<br />

definition the same, and singular. What happens w<strong>ith</strong> the<br />

fulfillment of a prophecy (and Rosset suggests that, in this<br />

respect, all reality is structured like a prophecy) is that the<br />

expected event coincides w<strong>ith</strong> itself, and this is the very<br />

source of our surprise – for we have been expecting something<br />

di≠erent, albeit akin to it, the same thing, but not<br />

exactly like this.<br />

This is why, according to Rosset, the sentiment of being<br />

somehow deceived, which always accompanies the realization<br />

of prophecy, is itself the peak of illusion. There is a<br />

deception involved in this all right, but not where we see it:<br />

we are deceived by the very impression that we have been<br />

deceived (that something else should have happened). The<br />

only illusion here is the illusion that we have been cheated,<br />

and that the realized event took the place of “something<br />

else.” (Here we come across the logic exposed by Lec’s aphorism<br />

again: “Who knows what Columbus might have discovered<br />

had America not blocked his way!”)<br />

We could say that, for Rosset, the real is out there as<br />

singular and unproblematic in itself, indistinguishable from<br />

its meaning. The other meaning (which can remain unspecified)<br />

is the result of the subjective will to illusion that

Hurra! Ihre Datei wurde hochgeladen und ist bereit für die Veröffentlichung.

Erfolgreich gespeichert!

Leider ist etwas schief gelaufen!