10.06.2023 Views

(Studies in German Literature Linguistics and Culture) Rolf J

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

INTRODUCTION: BENJAMIN’S ACTUALITY

13

which Benjamin’s legacy may come to fruition. In a recent essay on the

possibilities and limitations of actualizing Benjamin’s theory of art, Peter

Bürger has proposed that our era may not be the one in which Benjamin’s

thoughts can attain a higher degree of actuality than in their own time. 22

In Bürger’s opinion, the May 1968 uprisings in Paris, when students

and workers appropriated surrealist calls for the integration of imagination

and desire into political reality, may have been the last Benjaminian

“now-time” to date. At that critical moment, surrealist theory, Bürger

believes, did attain a higher degree of actuality than it had achieved in the

1920s, when the first surrealist manifesto was written. He maintains that

no such past is in sight that could be redeemed in our own time, because

a comprehensive perspective on how to rescue a segment of tradition

seems to be shrinking. Bürger’s example is the faithfully reconstructed

Frauenkirche in Dresden. For him, this famous centerpiece of Dresden’s

celebrated Baroque panorama appears like an isolated monument within

Socialist prefabricated housing complexes and the clumsy 1990s architecture

surrounding it. Although he concedes that the church (which was

financed by a huge popular fund-raising initiative) has promoted a sense

of social collectivity among the population, he denies that it is the spirit of

the Baroque that has contributed to this collective identity formulation.

Bürger’s pessimistic position rests largely on his assumption that Benjamin

lived at a time when, in the organic growth through history of cities

like Paris, the experience of tradition as a lived reality could still be taken

for granted. It was precisely this ubiquitous presence of genuine tradition,

Bürger argues, that allowed Benjamin to propose radical breaks with the

past. By contrast, he contends, our own time has lost this sense of a lived

tradition. Instead of detecting a period of the past whose analysis would

really enlighten the present, cultural studies, unable to resist political

interference in educational institutions and capitalism’s commodification

of culture, has lost its faith in the power of tradition and instead appropriates

its objects arbitrarily. Consequently, Bürger doubts that the entire

oeuvre of Benjamin, in all its diversity and contradictions, can be incorporated

into our present; rather, only selected motifs of this thought may be

taken up and continued. Thus Benjamin’s methodological reflections, for

instance his theoretical analysis of the historicity of auratic art, may promote

new ways of thinking about culture. Bürger appeals to the academic

establishment to face this dire situation in order to regain a concept of

tradition that allows for a new, meaningful engagement with works of

the past. He concludes rather vaguely with the unanswered question of

how Benjamin, an advocate of historical rupture who nonetheless thinks

in terms of a lived tradition, might have responded to our petty-minded

attitude (“Kleinmütigkeit”). 23

Bürger’s ambivalence toward Benjamin’s actualization, it seems to

me, stands on shaky feet. Problematically equating a meaningful attitude

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!