10.06.2023 Views

(Studies in German Literature Linguistics and Culture) Rolf J

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

50

DOMINIK FINKELDE

and idealistic” 8 academic epistemological activities. The prologue does

not try to revive forms of uncritical, pre-Kantian metaphysics. Instead it

reveals Benjamin’s struggle to enlarge an undialectical and “bourgeois”

notion of reason with metaphysical gestures of speech that reverberate in

the words “monad” and “idea.” One could even be tempted to say that

Benjamin tries intentionally to stress and overburden the vault of intellectual

(occidental) reason with these premodern terms of philosophy, in

order to explore new lines of thought.

In 1924 he writes to Scholem: “Du wirst [in der Vorrede] seit der

Arbeit ‘Über Sprache überhaupt und über die Sprache des Menschen’

zum ersten Male wieder so etwas wie einen erkenntnistheoretischen Versuch

finden” (Briefe, 346–47; You will find [in the prologue] something

like an epistemological essay for the first time again since my work “On

Language as Such and on the Language of Man”). And after having finished

the prologue, Benjamin writes: “Diese Einleitung ist eine maßlose

Chuzpe — nämlich nicht mehr und nicht weniger als Prologomena zur

Erkenntnistheorie” (Briefe, 372; This introduction is an excessive chutzpah

— it is nothing less and nothing more than prologomena to a theory

of cognition.) Of significance is, as mentioned before, the Platonic “idea.”

But in contrast to Plato, Benjamin tries to provide this term (which is traditionally

associated with an abstract entity) with a new facet that takes

into account, as Bernd Witte writes: “history . . . to a relevant degree.” 9

Hence Benjamin converts the “idea” from a metaphysical and abstract

notion into a model of an inductive procedure that starts from “historical

fields of gravitation” (Winfried Menninghaus), 10 comprising constellations,

which are considered more elusive than are static assemblages. In the

elaboration of these never fixed or fixable “constellations” — which touch

all kinds of different notions on which Benjamin will focus his attention:

“melancholy,” “honor,” the “sovereign,” or the “martyr” — it will become

obvious that the visibility of these constellations does not lead the reader

of the Trauerspiel book to clearly defined classifications of them, purified,

so to speak, of historical arbitrariness. Benjamin says of these ideas/constellations

that they are not “Inbegriffe von Regeln” (GS I.1:224; “simply

the sum total of certain sets of rules,” Origin, 44). They might even

not be “einem jeden Drama . . . kommensurabel” (GS I.1:224; “to any

and every drama . . . in a way commensurable,” Origin, 44). 11 They make

no claim “eine Anzahl gegebener Dichtungen auf Grund irgendwelcher

Gemeinsamkeiten ‘unter’ sich zu begreifen” (GS I.1:224; “to embrace a

number of given works of literature on the basis of certain features that

are common to them,” Origin, 44). By contrast, “ideas” become visible

by constellations manifesting themselves through phenomena, but they

cannot — through these same phenomena — be converted into propositional

matter. 12 In a sense the notion of “idea” sends us back, as Menninghaus

shows, to what Benjamin called in his early text “Über Sprache

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!