12.07.2015 Views

The Clinical Guide to Supportive and Palliative Care for HIV/AIDS

The Clinical Guide to Supportive and Palliative Care for HIV/AIDS

The Clinical Guide to Supportive and Palliative Care for HIV/AIDS

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

A <strong>Clinical</strong> <strong>Guide</strong> <strong>to</strong> <strong>Supportive</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Palliative</strong> <strong>Care</strong> <strong>for</strong> <strong>HIV</strong>/<strong>AIDS</strong> • Chapter 17: Ethical Issuesnoted, “there are no agreed-upon <strong>and</strong> validated st<strong>and</strong>ards or measurement instruments <strong>for</strong> healthcare providers <strong>to</strong> assess suffering <strong>and</strong> <strong>to</strong> discriminate how much there is. Similarly, there are noclear interventions that should be instituted <strong>and</strong> no clear underst<strong>and</strong>ing of when adequate palliativemeasures26 picas<strong>for</strong> suffering have been tried <strong>and</strong> failed.” 6 This uncertainty over the notion ofsuffering has important ethical implications in the delivery of palliative medicine, <strong>and</strong> we shallreturn <strong>to</strong> it when we discuss the practice of terminal sedation, below.Much of palliative medicine is focused on the phenomenological interests of patients at the endof life. But the nonphenomenological interests of these patients should not be ignored. <strong>The</strong>seare interests that are not well characterized in terms of maintaining the patient’s com<strong>for</strong>t. Apatient’s interest in having his privacy respected or in remaining alert even if his pain is not fullycontrolled are examples of such nonphenomenological interests. <strong>The</strong>se are discussed here becauserecent studies suggest that it is easy <strong>for</strong> clinicians <strong>to</strong> overlook them. 7 Taking these interestsseriously often requires clinicians <strong>to</strong> engage in active deliberation with their patients abouttheir treatment options.<strong>The</strong> two theoretical ideals of palliative medicine that have been discussed—the ideal of honoringthe dignity of the patient <strong>and</strong> the ideal of promoting the patient’s well-being—will sometimescome in<strong>to</strong> conflict. Not everything that furthers the interests of a patient is compatiblewith honoring him as a being worthy of respect. Determining how <strong>to</strong> respond appropriately <strong>to</strong>these potential conflicts <strong>for</strong>ms an important part of the ethics of palliative medicine.MEDIATING PRINCIPLES■ <strong>The</strong> theoretical ideals of palliative medicine guide clinicians in determining whichinterventions <strong>and</strong> treatment options are appropriate <strong>for</strong> their patients. But, on their own, theseideals cannot resolve the ethical problems that arise in the palliative care setting. <strong>The</strong>se situationsrequire recourse <strong>to</strong> ethical or mediating principles. <strong>The</strong> term mediating is used because theyintercede between the theoretical ideals discussed above <strong>and</strong> the concrete cases cliniciansencounter.<strong>The</strong>re are several important ethical principles that are relevant <strong>to</strong> the practice of palliativemedicine. This chapter will discuss three of them: 1) the Principle of Deliberation, 2) the Ruleof Double Effect, <strong>and</strong> 3) the Principle of Proportionality. Each of these principles has beendiscussed in the medical ethics literature. 9–15 However, they have not been discussed systematicallyin the context of palliative medicine <strong>and</strong> in the treatment of patients living with <strong>HIV</strong>/<strong>AIDS</strong>.Be<strong>for</strong>e discussing these principles a few words of caution are in order. First, the three principlesthat we shall discuss are not the only ethical principles relevant <strong>to</strong> palliative medicine.Given the space constraints of this chapter, we cannot present an exhaustive discussion of theseprinciples. However, the three principles that we will discuss are very important; <strong>and</strong> an underst<strong>and</strong>ingof them should provide an underst<strong>and</strong>ing of how ethical principles can be applied <strong>to</strong>concrete cases in palliative medicine. Second, some of the principles that we will discuss—<strong>and</strong>in particular the rule of double effect—are controversial. We shall, however, indicate <strong>to</strong> thereader when we advance claims that not all medical ethicists would agree with <strong>and</strong> we shallprovide references <strong>to</strong> alternative points of view.XVIIU.S. Department of Health <strong>and</strong> Human Services • Health Resources <strong>and</strong> Services Administration • <strong>HIV</strong>/<strong>AIDS</strong> Bureau 351

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!