12.07.2015 Views

The Clinical Guide to Supportive and Palliative Care for HIV/AIDS

The Clinical Guide to Supportive and Palliative Care for HIV/AIDS

The Clinical Guide to Supportive and Palliative Care for HIV/AIDS

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

A <strong>Clinical</strong> <strong>Guide</strong> <strong>to</strong> <strong>Supportive</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Palliative</strong> <strong>Care</strong> <strong>for</strong> <strong>HIV</strong>/<strong>AIDS</strong> • Chapter 17: Ethical Issues<strong>The</strong> Principle of Proportionality<strong>The</strong> rule of double effect is somewhat controversial. Not every medical ethicist believes thatit is as26importantpicas<strong>to</strong> medical practice as we have suggested. 15 But the fourth condition in therule of double effect—the one that specifies that a physician must act <strong>for</strong> a proportionatelygrave reason—is widely accepted even by those who reject the rule of double effect. <strong>The</strong>re<strong>for</strong>eit can <strong>and</strong> should be considered on its own terms. So unders<strong>to</strong>od, we shall refer <strong>to</strong> it as theprinciple of proportionality.This principle is very important <strong>to</strong> palliative medicine. A number of writers have appealed <strong>to</strong>this principle in their explorations of when, <strong>and</strong> under what conditions, a physician’s obligation12, 25<strong>to</strong> relieve terminal suffering may justifiably override his or her obligation <strong>to</strong> prevent harm.According <strong>to</strong> Timothy Quill, Bernard Lo, <strong>and</strong> Dan Brock, <strong>for</strong> example, the concept of proportionalityrequires that the risk of causing harm bear a direct relationship <strong>to</strong> the danger <strong>and</strong> immediacyof the patient’s situation <strong>and</strong> expected benefit of the intervention. 25 <strong>The</strong>se writers haveproposed the following <strong>for</strong>mulation of the proportionality principle <strong>for</strong> regulating physicians’use of vigorous pharmacological measures in the palliative care setting:[T]he greater the patient’s suffering, the greater risk the physician can take ofpotentially contributing <strong>to</strong> the patient’s death, so long as the patient underst<strong>and</strong>s<strong>and</strong> accepts the risk. 25This <strong>for</strong>mulation of the principle, however, does not specify what type (or types) of sufferingjustifies a physician’s use of pharmacological interventions <strong>to</strong> treat suffering. It simply instructsphysicians <strong>to</strong> sum up the <strong>to</strong>tal amount or intensity of the suffering their patients are experiencing.In this <strong>for</strong>mulation all terminal suffering is on equal footing <strong>and</strong> it is all subject <strong>to</strong> therequirements of proportionality.This principle of proportionality can be extended <strong>and</strong> refined by considering the theoreticalideal of promoting patient well-being <strong>and</strong> distinguishing between different kinds of pain <strong>and</strong>suffering <strong>and</strong> the different sorts of therapeutic interventions they may require. For example, apatient living with <strong>HIV</strong>/<strong>AIDS</strong> who is nearing the end of life may experience suffering that resultsfrom his terminal condition as well as suffering that results from his own reflection on his condition.Suppose, <strong>for</strong> example, that this patient blames himself <strong>for</strong> his illness <strong>and</strong> this causes himgreat inner turmoil. <strong>The</strong> resulting psychosocial suffering may be as intense as, or even moreintense than, the pain <strong>and</strong> suffering caused by his underlying physiological condition. It wouldbe a mistake, however, simply <strong>to</strong> sum up his suffering as if it were all the same. Some of thesuffering that this patient experiences—what we have referred <strong>to</strong> here as psychosocial suffering—isnot appropriately managed by aggressive pharmacological measures. Unless thesethoughts are symp<strong>to</strong>ms of major depression, the patient’s psychosocial suffering should be managedby appropriate psychological or spiritual counseling.This point is important <strong>for</strong> all patients in need of palliative care, but it has particular <strong>for</strong>ce whenapplied <strong>to</strong> patients living with <strong>HIV</strong>/<strong>AIDS</strong>. Recent studies suggest that a high proportion of patientsliving with <strong>HIV</strong>/<strong>AIDS</strong> who desire euthanasia or assisted suicide do so <strong>for</strong> reasons otherthan the need <strong>to</strong> avoid pain. 6, 26 Depression, hopelessness, psychological anguish, distress causedby stigmatizing events related <strong>to</strong> their <strong>HIV</strong> status, <strong>and</strong> loss of community have been identified askey fac<strong>to</strong>rs contributing <strong>to</strong> the suffering of these patients. 26 <strong>The</strong>se <strong>for</strong>ms of suffering, however,are not appropriately managed by high-dose narcotics. 14, 27 This strongly suggests that physi-356U.S. Department of Health <strong>and</strong> Human Services • Health Resources <strong>and</strong> Services Administration • <strong>HIV</strong>/<strong>AIDS</strong> Bureau

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!