30.06.2013 Views

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

I contend that because we seek certainty, we have called on the courts to adjudicate the<br />

decisions. However, legal decision makers (like others) cannot establish a definitive<br />

answer to the fundamental human questions raised. Judges working within positivist<br />

frameworks also seek certainty, which they have found largely by deferring back to<br />

medical solutions. I use best interest case law to support and develop my arguments. I<br />

conclude by suggesting that the only way to break the philosophical impasse is by<br />

recognising, accepting and revealing the values which inform and guide best interest<br />

determinations.<br />

The process of revolution<br />

In chapter two I drew parallels with Kuhn’s process of scientific revolution to<br />

demonstrate how values become objectified in law. To briefly re-cap, when a new<br />

paradigm is created in science, it must be valued by sufficient numbers of the relevant<br />

community for it to be successful. Because the new paradigm is incompatible with the<br />

old paradigm, there is a period of conflict. In the period of conflict, there is debate,<br />

during which the opportunity arises for the expression of values about the competing<br />

paradigms. The relevant communities make their choices and the new world view<br />

succeeds if there is sufficient support. The revolution is complete once the new<br />

paradigm is completely normalised within the scientific community. This process may<br />

take many years and even across generations.<br />

The new paradigm<br />

A new paradigm is emerging in medical decision making. Traditionally, health care<br />

treatment decisions for incapacitated adults were left to the discretion of health<br />

professionals. Social conventions promoting a paternalistic “doctor knows best”<br />

approach flourished in an environment in which medical professionals were accorded<br />

God-like status (Brazier, 1992). Under these conditions, treatment decisions were the<br />

domain of doctors, with an assumption that the ethical principle of beneficence<br />

underpinned their intentions (Eastman & Peay, 1999, p. 28). Medicine was seen by<br />

some as a new religion, doctors were seen as magicians and there was increasing<br />

medicalisation of the events of our everyday lives (Kennedy, 1981). In this<br />

139

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!