30.06.2013 Views

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

For years, health professionals have provided certainty, basing their decisions on<br />

medical science and ‘clinical judgement’. Questions about, for example, who should be<br />

given renal replacement therapy is couched in medical terms such as prognosis, clinical<br />

benefit and scientific evidence. However, the period of uncertainty between the old<br />

paradigm and the new paradigm has resulted in the destabilisation of traditional social<br />

conventions and revealed the certainty of clinical judgement as a façade.<br />

Consider again Sartre’s portrayal of our human response to the realisation of our<br />

freedom and choice to make decisions about the situations that confront us in daily life.<br />

Through his fictional character Antoinne, Sartre portrayed our response to this freedom<br />

and choice as anguish and nausea (Sartre, 1962). Antoinne’s response seemed both<br />

extreme and ridiculous in the context of ordinary events in our daily lives, like ordering<br />

a drink in a café or observing an oak tree in a park.<br />

Imagine instead that you have to make a decision whether to permanently remove the<br />

reproductive capacity of a young woman with learning disability, or to end the life of<br />

young man in a persistent vegetative state by discontinuing food and hydration. Sartre’s<br />

representation comes to life. The enormity and finality of the decision and the absence<br />

of complete certainty about whether your decision is right or wrong renders a response<br />

of almost dizzying anxiety completely understandable.<br />

This leaves us on shaky ground. We know this. We also know that when we make<br />

choices, we have to take responsibility for them. So we attempt to create certainty. As<br />

Sartre suggests, in an attempt to achieve certainty, we may use methods of<br />

objectification. And if we then detach our own subjective judgement from the process<br />

what results is bad faith. This tendency has been observed in health professionals.<br />

Research tells us that doctors shroud value judgements in technical justifications<br />

(Spiers, 1997). This in itself is not bad faith. But what if the objectification is used to<br />

avoid the complexity of the decisions or to remove their subjective selves from the<br />

process? Sayers and Perera (2002) examined end of life treatment decisions by general<br />

practitioners and geriatricians in response to case studies. Each case study concerned<br />

whether to initiate acute, routine medical treatment for elderly people with terminal<br />

illnesses without which they would die. For instance, the doctors were asked whether a<br />

141

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!