30.06.2013 Views

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Dworkin’s response appears to be an attempt to theorise what, in positivist legal<br />

systems, is the unrecognised evaluative component of judicial interpretation. However,<br />

while acknowledging that the theoretical perspective of actors is influential on their<br />

interpretation of law, and recognising the relative nature of judicial discretion (1970, p.<br />

45), Dworkin denies any subjective component (1994, p. 474). Instead, Dworkin argues<br />

that whether legal interpretation is subjective or objective “depends on the underlying<br />

claims about the purpose of the enterprise” (p. 474). For example, if we think there is a<br />

possible right answer to questions of justice, then we will also think that there are right<br />

answers to questions of law (p. 475).<br />

Dworkin fervently defends his position on ethical objectivism (1986, p. 45–86; 1994, p.<br />

475). In doing so, he follows in a long history of rationalist theoretical traditions which<br />

support his objectivist position. He employs philosophical argument to discount the<br />

sceptical view that there can be no moral absolutes. For example, Dworkin argues that<br />

matters of right and wrong about slavery are linked to belief rather than opinion. He<br />

argues that moral beliefs can be objective: that they are not simply matters of opinion<br />

as, say, your favourite ice cream flavour. Dworkin demonstrates his position by<br />

examining whether abortion can be described as right or wrong, or whether it is just a<br />

matter of opinion.<br />

It is certainly logically possible to take up a fully sceptical position<br />

about abortion, or any other matter of political or social justice. But<br />

then you have to give up your own opinion. And most people confronted<br />

with that choice will give up bad philosophy rather than intensely held<br />

convictions.<br />

Dworkin, 1994, p. 475<br />

Unfortunately, what Dworkin and others hold as good philosophy does not reflect<br />

reality. Influential theoretical perspectives of law have an inescapable basis in ethics<br />

(Knowles, 2001, p. 2). For example, according to Mill, the only purpose for which<br />

power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilised community, against<br />

his will, is to prevent harm to others (Mill, 1972, p. 78). As such, they are based in<br />

values. This philosophical distinction is crucial to my thesis. If the theories which guide<br />

and inform what Dworkin calls the “underlying legal enterprise” are viewed as<br />

objective, the result is not value-free decision making process. Instead, values of<br />

47

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!