30.06.2013 Views

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Kant’s philosophy is uncompromising, proposing that the moral law specifies simply<br />

what must be done, not what must be done to achieve an objective (Dickerson, 2004, p.<br />

66). Kant was concerned with moral duty, not with the consequences of actions, and<br />

gave the example of lying to demonstrate his theory (2002, p. 68). “I ought not to lie if I<br />

want to maintain my reputation”. This formulation is what Kant calls a hypothetical<br />

imperative. The action is guided not by the establishment of a moral duty not to lie.<br />

Instead, the motivation for action lay in the consequence of action rather than in the<br />

duty to follow the moral law per se. Kant argued against a hypothetical imperative in<br />

which the motivation for action lay in its consequence. He argued instead for the<br />

categorical imperative. According to the categorical imperative, the moral agent should<br />

not be concerned with lying in order to achieve an objective. They should simply be<br />

concerned with the maxim; “I ought not to lie”.<br />

Autonomy and freedom of will are central to Kant’s moral philosophy (2002, p. 67 and<br />

p. 74). Kant argued that normal adults are capable of being self-governing in moral<br />

matters, and that through reason, we impose moral laws on ourselves which give rise to<br />

obligations and the necessity to act in certain ways (Schneewind, 1992, p. 310). Kant<br />

thought that an action done for the sake of duty, which is caused by a good will, cannot<br />

be done out of desire or natural inclination (Thomson, 2003, p. 64). The duty is<br />

prescribed by reason.<br />

It is evident from the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals that Kant viewed pure<br />

reason as solely deductive, excluding all sensory and empirical knowledge to establish<br />

a right action.<br />

Every one must admit that a law has to carry with it absolute necessity<br />

if it is to be valid morally – valid, that is, as a ground of obligation; that<br />

the command ‘Thou shalt not lie’ could not hold merely for men, other<br />

rational beings having no obligation to abide by it – and similarly with<br />

all other genuine moral laws; that here consequently the ground of<br />

obligation must be looked for, not in the nature of man nor in the<br />

circumstances of the world in which he is placed, but solely a priori in<br />

the concepts of pure reason.<br />

Kant, 2002, p. 21<br />

53

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!