30.06.2013 Views

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

stating that “the Court of Appeal would be free, having regard to requirements of<br />

certainty in law, to depart from a covering decision of its own” (Denning [1966] cited<br />

Aldridge, 1984, p. 188). Since then, the House of Lords and the Court of Appeal are no<br />

longer bound by their own rules of precedent and may depart from previous decisions<br />

“when it is considered right to do so”.<br />

These observations indicate some of the ambiguities and inconsistencies surrounding<br />

precedent. However, what emerges from this brief examination is that legal analogy, as<br />

with all processes of reasoning, is necessarily dependent on values. Firstly, the judge is<br />

required to decide whether to be bound by the laws of precedent, or whether they are<br />

simply rules of practice. Secondly, they must evaluate the facts and details of one case<br />

and decide whether it is applicable to the case at hand. Thirdly, the judge must evaluate<br />

to what extent the rules or principles in the previous case are binding. And fourthly, if<br />

members of the House of Lords, they must evaluate whether it is ‘right’ to follow<br />

previous precedent. As Aldridge suggests, rules of precedent owe their binding nature<br />

to judges’ attitudes to “their own dealings and those of their brethren” (1984, p. 200).<br />

The judge<br />

Crucial to value-free legal method is not only the employment of rational and scientific<br />

method, but the perception of the neutrality of the judge. The common view that law is<br />

a system of rules goes hand in hand with the role of judges to neutrally and objectively<br />

apply the law. It is precisely because judges are not robots or machines that the<br />

necessary interpretation and application in anything but the most straight forward case<br />

is possible. Despite the development of mechanisms which aim to objectify judicial<br />

interpretation, there remains considerable judicial discretion particularly where the law<br />

is unclear and open textured.<br />

Lord Devlin describes his perception of this component of his role as a Lord of Appeal<br />

in the highest court of the English legal system. Lord Devlin paints a picture of the<br />

judge as the epitome of an English gentleman; a “spokesman for the ordinary citizen”<br />

(p. 22) whose role is an extension of a jury and his judgement an “elaboration of a<br />

jury’s verdict” (p. 27). In relation to the ordinary man, Lord Devlin talks of judges<br />

44

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!