30.06.2013 Views

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

View/Open - Scholarly Commons Home

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Decision making is further inhibited because one of the two options is already firmly<br />

established as preferable by the health professionals involved. Historically the judiciary<br />

have proven reluctant to question the clinical decision making of health professionals<br />

(Keywood, 1995, p. 128; Sheldon, 1997, p. 75-103). Keywood describes the “rather<br />

special relationship” which exists between the medical profession and the courts, with<br />

judges inclined to respect their clinical judgement and who have declined to perform<br />

close scrutiny, particularly in matters of diagnosis and treatment (1995, p. 127). Case<br />

law is littered with examples, but the following is representative.<br />

I find it difficult to conceive of a situation where it would be a proper<br />

exercise of the jurisdiction to make an order positively requiring a<br />

doctor to adopt a particular course of treatment… unless the doctor<br />

himself or herself was asking the court to make such an order.<br />

Re J [1993] (England) Balcombe LJ, cited Kennedy & Grubb, 2000, p. 821<br />

Whilst the new paradigm challenging unfettered medical decision making discretion<br />

has resulted in cases coming before the courts, the common law doctrine of precedent<br />

has promoted and supported traditional approaches. Re F [1990] established best<br />

interest decisions as primarily medically determined. This ensured that the same<br />

approach was followed in the many cases that followed both in England and<br />

internationally. For example, one of the first cases in New Zealand to employ the best<br />

interest test was Auckland Area Health Board v Attorney General [1993]. This case was<br />

an application by doctors of the intensive care unit of the Auckland Hospital for a<br />

declaration clarifying whether they would be guilty of culpable homicide under the<br />

Crimes Act 1961 (NZ) if they withdrew the life support system of a patient with an<br />

extreme case of Guillain-Barre syndrome. The test was invoked, and finding the<br />

withdrawal of treatment in accordance with a responsible body of medical opinion, the<br />

actions of health professionals were declared lawful.<br />

Reverting to the fact-centred medical approach achieves a veneer of certainty and<br />

value-neutrality in the form of empirical evidence, clinical judgement and the evidence<br />

of experts. But this does not alter the evaluative nature of the decisions, and the values<br />

which guide them do not disappear. Instead they are hidden behind the combined<br />

illusion of objective legal process and medical science. Is this an example of bad faith?<br />

147

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!