10.05.2015 Views

Human Dignity and Bioethics

Human Dignity and Bioethics

Human Dignity and Bioethics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Defending <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Dignity</strong> | 301<br />

in accepting risks <strong>and</strong> discomforts, his philanthropic desire to contribute<br />

to a worthy cause, <strong>and</strong> his generosity of time <strong>and</strong> trouble in<br />

embracing activities from which he will receive no direct benefit.<br />

In these domains of clinical medicine <strong>and</strong> research involving<br />

human subjects, appeals to human dignity, while tacitly employing<br />

an ideal of proper treatment <strong>and</strong> respect, function explicitly <strong>and</strong><br />

mainly as bulwarks against abuse: patients should not be reduced<br />

to “thing-hood” or treated as mere bodies; research subjects should<br />

not be utilized as mere means or treated only as experimental animals.<br />

This “negative” function of the concept of human dignity in<br />

these domains makes perfect sense, inasmuch as it is intended—<strong>and</strong><br />

needed—to restrain the strong in their dealings with the weak. It<br />

makes even more sense once we remember the origins of modern<br />

biomedical ethics: a concern for human dignity hovers over all of<br />

modern biomedical ethics owing to the world’s horror at the Nazi<br />

atrocities, atrocities in which German scientists <strong>and</strong> German doctors<br />

were deeply implicated. They more than lent a h<strong>and</strong> with eugenic<br />

sterilization, barbaric human experimentation, <strong>and</strong> mass extermination<br />

of the “unfit”—all undertaken, mind you, in order to produce “a<br />

more perfect human.” The rise to prominence of the idea of “human<br />

dignity” in post-World-War-II Europe, expressed in the laws of many<br />

nations <strong>and</strong> especially in the United Nations’ Universal Declaration of<br />

<strong>Human</strong> Rights, was surely intended to ensure that no human beings<br />

should ever again be so abused, degraded, <strong>and</strong> dehumanized—<strong>and</strong>,<br />

of course, annihilated.<br />

But a more robust notion of human dignity is needed when we<br />

turn from these traditional domains of medical ethics to the moral<br />

challenges raised by new biotechnological powers <strong>and</strong> the novel purposes<br />

to which they are being put, <strong>and</strong> when we turn from concerns<br />

with abuse of power that the strong inflict upon the weak to concerns<br />

with ethically dubious uses of powers that the strong—indeed, most<br />

of us—will choose to exercise for <strong>and</strong> on ourselves. Our desires for a<br />

better life do not end with health, <strong>and</strong> the uses of biotechnology are<br />

not limited to therapy. Its powers to alter the workings of body <strong>and</strong><br />

mind are attractive not only to the sick <strong>and</strong> suffering, but to everyone<br />

who desires to look younger, perform better, feel happier, or become<br />

more “perfect.”<br />

We have already entered the age of biotechnical enhancement:

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!