28.03.2013 Views

Bernard Shaw's Remarkable Religion: A Faith That Fits the Facts

Bernard Shaw's Remarkable Religion: A Faith That Fits the Facts

Bernard Shaw's Remarkable Religion: A Faith That Fits the Facts

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

190 <strong>Bernard</strong> Shaw’s <strong>Remarkable</strong> <strong>Religion</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ologians, on whom <strong>the</strong> scientists look down with more or less tolerant<br />

condescension. Not surprisingly, Popper’s notion has been absorbed<br />

into <strong>the</strong> orthodoxy of science and is incorporated into <strong>the</strong> image many<br />

scientists have of what <strong>the</strong>y do. It is cited in this way, for instance, by<br />

Stephen Hawking in his popular book A Brief History of Time (10). So<br />

while Popper attacked <strong>the</strong> intellectual arrogance of Logical Positivism, he<br />

flattered <strong>the</strong> scientists by portraying science as ruthlessly skeptical. After<br />

all, it was philosophers, not scientists, who had insisted that science produced<br />

a body of certain fact. And Popper makes explicit what is implied by<br />

Shaw’s view of what science should be.<br />

Thomas Kuhn<br />

Then came Thomas Kuhn, a historian as well as a philosopher of science, to<br />

point out that this is not <strong>the</strong> way science actually works. It could not work,<br />

in fact, because falsification is far more difficult than <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory implies.<br />

The reason is suggested by <strong>the</strong> old proverb “The exception proves <strong>the</strong><br />

rule.” The sense of “proves” is “tests” (as in “proving ground”), and <strong>the</strong><br />

meaning of <strong>the</strong> saying is that every rule is tested by apparent exceptions.<br />

Galileo’s rule that light and heavy objects fall at <strong>the</strong> same rate is not falsified<br />

by <strong>the</strong> fact that under normal circumstances a fea<strong>the</strong>r and a brick do<br />

not fall at <strong>the</strong> same rate. Air pressure affects <strong>the</strong> objects differently, so <strong>the</strong><br />

rule becomes manifest (with those particular objects) only in a vacuum.<br />

The trouble is that in nature many different factors influence <strong>the</strong> course of<br />

events, and one can never be certain, no matter how rigorously controlled<br />

<strong>the</strong> experiment may be, that all “hidden” factors have been eliminated. If a<br />

single counterinstance were always fatal to a scientific <strong>the</strong>ory, science<br />

would get nowhere.<br />

Science actually moves in a way sharply different from <strong>the</strong> orthodox<br />

myth of scientific progress. Science is historically a dialectical process in<br />

which periods of “normal science” are punctuated by “revolutions.” The<br />

accepted myths about scientific thinking come closest to being realized<br />

during <strong>the</strong> revolutions, but normal science, which is what most scientists<br />

do most of <strong>the</strong> time, is entirely different. This historical rhythm is controlled<br />

by “paradigms,” models of <strong>the</strong> natural world, or aspects of it, that<br />

serve as a kind of archetype on which scientific investigation is based.<br />

“Paradigm” is somewhat loosely defined and is used to represent both <strong>the</strong><br />

fundamental assumptions that are shared by nearly all scientists and <strong>the</strong><br />

more narrowly applicable models appealed to by specialists. They are

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!