28.03.2013 Views

Bernard Shaw's Remarkable Religion: A Faith That Fits the Facts

Bernard Shaw's Remarkable Religion: A Faith That Fits the Facts

Bernard Shaw's Remarkable Religion: A Faith That Fits the Facts

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

40 <strong>Bernard</strong> Shaw’s <strong>Remarkable</strong> <strong>Religion</strong><br />

ceived little attention. Actually, it is a description of Shaw’s intellectual<br />

development seen as a dialectical argument.<br />

Shaw’s Intellectual Development<br />

The realist (Shaw), although brought up in an environment of conventional<br />

hypocritical piety, sees through such sham as soon as his critical<br />

faculties develop. He recognizes that many of <strong>the</strong> institutions revered by<br />

those around him are nothing but illusions. He sees that Falstaff was right,<br />

and “honor” is nothing but a word; <strong>the</strong>re is nothing in <strong>the</strong> objective, observable<br />

world that corresponds to <strong>the</strong> word “honor.” He recognizes <strong>the</strong><br />

childishness of Bible-worship and <strong>the</strong> inconsistencies and improbabilities<br />

of conventional religion. He becomes aware of an unconventional belief<br />

system that proposes to be consistent and honest. It is based vaguely in<br />

something called science; Shaw calls it rationalism and materialism. It is a<br />

very refreshing religion for a disillusioned realist who thirsts most of all<br />

for things as <strong>the</strong>y are, not simply as we might cravenly wish <strong>the</strong>m to be. It<br />

has one glaring flaw: in confusing “objectivity” with “realism,” it fails to<br />

acknowledge what is inside as well as what is outside.<br />

Rationalism, for Shaw, is virtually indistinguishable from what philosophers<br />

call utilitarian ethics. “Rationalists” attempted to discard superstition<br />

and live entirely by <strong>the</strong> principles of reason. They concluded that a<br />

rationally developed value system could be derived entirely through a<br />

simple calculus of pain and pleasure. Schopenhauer’s great insight—that<br />

will, not reason, was <strong>the</strong> source of human action—was hopelessly contaminated<br />

in Shaw’s view by his acceptance of <strong>the</strong> “Rationalist-Mercantilist<br />

error of valuing life according to its individual profits in pleasure” (Major<br />

Critical Essays 310). 1 Shaw saw that Schopenhauer did not understand<br />

<strong>the</strong> significance of his own insight, for will is not merely motive power but<br />

<strong>the</strong> source of all values: <strong>the</strong> pessimistic conclusion that will is a malign<br />

force is unjustified and self-contradictory. You cannot declare that will is<br />

bad because will is <strong>the</strong> foundation of all value: as Bertrand Russell put it,<br />

“Outside human desires <strong>the</strong>re is no moral standard” (“What I Believe”<br />

62). Shaw instinctively understood that all our values come not from outside<br />

but from inside ourselves; and in this he was in complete accord with<br />

recent philosophy: A. J. Ayer claims that one of <strong>the</strong> few twentieth-century<br />

notions on which philosophers now agree is that “<strong>the</strong>re is no such thing as<br />

an authoritative guide to moral judgement” (15). Both ethical judgments<br />

and those longings we think of as immoral or selfish come from <strong>the</strong> same<br />

place, from within ourselves; <strong>the</strong>y are aspects of what we want—of our

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!