28.03.2013 Views

Bernard Shaw's Remarkable Religion: A Faith That Fits the Facts

Bernard Shaw's Remarkable Religion: A Faith That Fits the Facts

Bernard Shaw's Remarkable Religion: A Faith That Fits the Facts

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Realism 31<br />

to be tied down to textbook definitions. One may get a better idea of what<br />

Shaw means by this oblique allusion to “Platonism” from his preface to<br />

Three Plays by Brieux, where he discusses <strong>the</strong> nature and purpose of dramatic<br />

realism. He thinks that Zola’s naturalism is self-defeating: Zola, he<br />

says, added gratuitous elements to his fiction to make it appear more like<br />

real events—that is, like things one might read in newspaper crime stories.<br />

“To all artists and Platonists he made it <strong>the</strong>reby very unreal; for to <strong>the</strong><br />

Platonist all accidents are unreal and negligible; but to <strong>the</strong> people he<br />

wanted to get at—<strong>the</strong> anti-artistic people—he made it readable” (xii). How<br />

a “Platonist” artist would proceed we may ga<strong>the</strong>r from Shaw’s praise of<br />

Brieux, whose method he contrasts to <strong>the</strong> true crime technique of Zola:<br />

But <strong>the</strong> great dramatist has . . . to interpret life. . . . Life as it occurs is<br />

senseless: a policeman may watch it . . . without learning as much of<br />

it or from it as a child or a nun may learn from a single play by Brieux.<br />

For it is <strong>the</strong> business of Brieux to pick out <strong>the</strong> significant incidents<br />

from <strong>the</strong> chaos of daily happenings, and arrange <strong>the</strong>m so that <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

relation to one ano<strong>the</strong>r becomes significant, thus changing us from<br />

bewildered spectators of a monstrous confusion to men intelligently<br />

conscious of <strong>the</strong> world and its destinies. (xxiv–xxv)<br />

Thus <strong>the</strong> sense one gets from this preface (written in 1909) is that “Platonism”<br />

for Shaw is a belief that <strong>the</strong> universe is orderly and comprehensible<br />

and that it is <strong>the</strong> business of <strong>the</strong> artist-philosopher to describe <strong>the</strong> order,<br />

not <strong>the</strong> accidents, of <strong>the</strong> world. The Quintessence and <strong>the</strong> comments about<br />

Nietzsche tell us that one can come to understand that order only through<br />

experience—through unreserved, intimate, and unqualified involvement.<br />

Order must be derived totally from experience and must never be imposed<br />

on experience. The task of <strong>the</strong> artist- philosopher is to get at those concrete<br />

facts that reveal <strong>the</strong> essential and avoid those that are merely incidental<br />

and accidental. Ideas are important, but <strong>the</strong>ir origin must be empirical, not<br />

a priori. To insist that this is nothing of what Plato had in mind would<br />

doubtless not give Shaw <strong>the</strong> least concern.<br />

The question that should concern us is whe<strong>the</strong>r Shaw had already<br />

adopted this particular form of “Platonism” in 1890 when he drafted what<br />

was to become The Quintessence of Ibsenism. Several critics have maintained<br />

that he had not. Wisenthal, Alfred Turco Jr., and o<strong>the</strong>rs have argued<br />

that, in Wisenthal’s words, “<strong>the</strong> general tendency in <strong>the</strong> 1891 Quintessence<br />

is to dismiss or attack all of those who live in a world of ideas” but that<br />

his attitude toward ideas, ideals, and idealists became increasingly favor-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!