28.03.2013 Views

Bernard Shaw's Remarkable Religion: A Faith That Fits the Facts

Bernard Shaw's Remarkable Religion: A Faith That Fits the Facts

Bernard Shaw's Remarkable Religion: A Faith That Fits the Facts

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

76 <strong>Bernard</strong> Shaw’s <strong>Remarkable</strong> <strong>Religion</strong><br />

Ibsen is also called to task for his use of <strong>the</strong> “contrivances” of <strong>the</strong> wellmade<br />

play. Such objections are utterly irrelevant. Ibsen was no more interested<br />

than Shaw in creating superficial photographic illusions of life—<br />

Candid Camera realism. He was exploring consciences, desires, and <strong>the</strong><br />

conflict of human wills. The revisionist criticism that seeks out <strong>the</strong> “contrivances”<br />

of <strong>the</strong> “well-made play” in <strong>the</strong> work of turn-of-<strong>the</strong>-century realists<br />

is fallacious as well as irrelevant because it is based on two dangerously<br />

erroneous assumptions. In <strong>the</strong> first place, all plays, like all o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

works of fiction, are contrived. They are consciously put toge<strong>the</strong>r to create<br />

an effect or to convey a message or both. This is true even of <strong>the</strong> most<br />

extreme “slice-of-life” naturalists, who are often so intent on creating <strong>the</strong><br />

illusion of reality that <strong>the</strong>y sacrifice honest observation to popular prejudice—such<br />

as <strong>the</strong> assumption that <strong>the</strong> nastier and dirtier something appears<br />

<strong>the</strong> more real it must be. Second, well-made plays were not contrived<br />

to appear contrived: <strong>the</strong>y were crafted to create <strong>the</strong> illusion of reality, an<br />

illusion fabricated from <strong>the</strong> expectations of <strong>the</strong> audience. They appear<br />

“contrived” to us because we do not share those expectations, but we<br />

should not imagine that whenever something in a play by Ibsen or Shaw<br />

reminds us that we are indeed in a <strong>the</strong>ater, that we have discovered a flaw<br />

in <strong>the</strong>ir realism. If it is a flaw, it is a lapse in illusionism, something often<br />

incompatible with critical realism.<br />

We need to suppress <strong>the</strong> temptation to apply <strong>the</strong> rule of commonsense<br />

realism to <strong>the</strong> plays of <strong>the</strong> realists, including Shaw, and to seek a more<br />

rigorous, as well as more appropriate, standard. The difficulty is that<br />

commonsense realism pervades our thinking about realism, and for good<br />

reasons. It is easy to slip from talking about <strong>the</strong> purposes of realism into<br />

discussions of its style, and when we think about a naturalistic style we are<br />

all too apt to think in illusionistic terms. So <strong>the</strong> confusion arises inevitably,<br />

in no small part out of <strong>the</strong> efforts of <strong>the</strong> most rigorously scientific realists<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves. Realism is first of all a way of viewing <strong>the</strong> world; it declares,<br />

like all serious artistic movements, that <strong>the</strong> function of art is to tell <strong>the</strong><br />

truth, and it has definite ideas about <strong>the</strong> nature of that truth. So <strong>the</strong> heart<br />

of literary realism is a philosophy, but that philosophy must generate new<br />

artistic forms or styles. Unfortunately, <strong>the</strong> new illusionist style favored by<br />

<strong>the</strong> realists actually obscured <strong>the</strong> ends to which it was presumably only a<br />

means.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!