12.12.2022 Views

BazermanMoore

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Bounded Ethicality 123

within firms such as Enron and its auditor, Arthur Andersen; gatekeepers within these

companies; and failed governmental regulation. Business leaders were blamed for their

role in the presumed ethical decline, and business schools were criticized for failing to

provide ethical training to future leaders.

The media implied that the key to stemming the tide of financial scandals was to

stop managers from deciding to engage in unethical behavior. This approach is broadly

consistent with the field of ethics, which focuses on deliberative decisions. In this section,

we will challenge this ethical perspective on corporate scandals. We are in favor of

changing the incentives of organizational actors to encourage more ethical behavior and

would be delighted to see genuine corporate criminals serve time in prison. But recent

research provides a compelling case that the vast majority of unethical behaviors occur

without the actors’ conscious intention to behave unethically.

We focus on the cognitive biases that lead honorable people to engage in unethical

behavior without realizing that they are doing so. The first half of this chapter examined

the ways in which fairness judgments depart from standard economic models. This second

half of the chapter considers how cognitive biases allow us to act in ways that contradict

our own intended standard of ethics. These deviations from our intended

standard are systematic and predictable, just as the biases from rationality discussed in

Chapters 2 through 6 are predictable and systematic. Rather than concentrating on intentionally

corrupt behavior, we will discuss recent research that identifies the types,

magnitudes, and causes of unethical behavior that occurs without the awareness of the

actor—what we refer to as bounded ethicality (Chugh, Bazerman, & Banaji, 2005). This

perspective diverges from the standard treatments of ethics, which assume the explicit

analysis of appropriate action by the individual, yet complements this traditional view.

Our central argument is that understanding and changing the ethicality of human

action requires going beyond the common assumption that ethically challenged behavior

results from people choosing self-rewarding behavior over doing what is right. The

assumption of the conscious agent as the sole determinant of human action has been

clearly refuted (Fiske, 2004). New evidence points to the limitations of the conscious

mind, while emphasizing the power of the unconscious mind to drive us to engage in

unethical behavior (Banaji & Bhaskar, 2000; Murnighan, Cantelon, & Elyashiv, 2004;

Wegner, 2002).

We use the term bounded ethicality to refer to the psychological processes that

lead people to engage in ethically questionable behaviors that are inconsistent with

their own preferred ethics. Bounded ethicality comes into play when an executive

makes a decision that not only harms others, but also is inconsistent with his or her

conscious beliefs and preferences. Managers develop protective cognitions that lead

them to engage in behaviors that they would condemn upon further reflection or

awareness. For example, Chapter 4 reviewed the omissions bias, which shows that people

feel less responsible for harms caused by inaction than for harms caused by action.

When managers become aware of an ethically questionable situation that is not formally

part of their responsibility and fail to get involved, they may be quick to justify

inaction as ethical, when greater reflection would prove inaction to be more harmful

than many errors of action. Chugh (2004) argues that bounded ethicality is exacerbated

by the high-paced demands of managerial life, which demand the speed and

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!