12.12.2022 Views

BazermanMoore

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

82 Chapter 4: Framing and the Reversal of Preferences

CONCLUSION AND INTEGRATION

The categories of framing effects and reversals of preference covered in this chapter

demonstrate some of the key findings in the field of behavioral decision research. The

Asian Disease Problem that opened the chapter is a particularly important problem in

the history of the field. Prior to this result and the development of Kahneman and

Tversky’s (1979) prospect theory, behavioral decision literature was largely ignored by

economists. Simon’s concept of bounded rationality, discussed in Chapter 1, was explained

away as a rational strategy, adapting for the costs of search. The heuristics and

biases explored in Chapter 2 were discounted for similar reasons. But the framing

effects described in this chapter showed people making dramatically different decisions

based on what even economists had to agree was normatively irrelevant information.

The Asian Disease Problem, which challenged the dominant economic paradigm

more than twenty-five years ago, is a cornerstone of the type of data that create a productive

dialogue between psychologists and economists. The numerous other framing

effects that have been documented continue this tradition and have contributed to the

growth of the fields of behavioral economics and behavioral finance.

One question that often emerges from these studies is whether or not these effects

generalize to the real world. Four editions ago, Max was optimistic about this question,

but did not have the data to be convincing. Since then, numerous excellent studies have

used framing effects to explain why taxi drivers drive more hours on slow days than on

busy ones (Camerer, Babcock, Loewenstein, & Thaler, 1997), why so many people pay

for line insurance on their telephones (Thaler & Ziemba, 1988), the conditions under

which negotiators are most likely to reach an impasse (see Chapter 10), and a wide

variety of investment mistakes (the topic of Chapter 8). Camerer (2000) also does an

excellent job of summarizing the strong evidence of the relevance of framing effects in

the real world.

Why does framing exert such a powerful effect on our judgments? The answer

cannot be the same one that we used to explain the biases covered in Chapter 2 and 3.

The biases in those chapters result from heuristic shortcuts in judgment. By comparison,

the striking aspect about framing and reference-point effects is that they suggest

the presence of underlying mental processes that are more complicated than a rational

decision maker would employ. Rational decision makers would simply seek to maximize

the expected value of their choices. Whether these outcomes represent gains or losses

would be irrelevant, and consideration of the outcome relative to the status quo would

be a superfluous consideration. Instead, we adjust to the status quo, and then think of

changes from that point as gains or losses.

Rayo and Becker (2007) present a persuasive explanation for why evolution programmed

us with extra machinery that impairs our decisions. According to their explanation,ourrelianceonframesandreferencepointstoassessoutcomesisanelegant

solution to a problematic biological constraint. The constraint is that our ‘‘subjective

utility scale’’—our ability to experience pleasure and pain—is not infinitely sensitive.

Was Bill Gates’s 50th billion dollar as satisfying as his first? Certainly not. The limited

sensitivity of our subjective utility scale is precisely the reason why we experience declining

marginal utility for both gains and losses, as we discussed earlier in this chapter.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!