12.07.2015 Views

Approaches to Quantum Gravity

Approaches to Quantum Gravity

Approaches to Quantum Gravity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The group field theory approach <strong>to</strong> <strong>Quantum</strong> <strong>Gravity</strong> 323vertex amplitude gives (in the non-degenerate sec<strong>to</strong>r) the cosine of the Reggeaction instead of the exponential of it. These properties suggest the interpretation[24] of the corresponding models as defining the <strong>Quantum</strong> <strong>Gravity</strong> analog of theHadamard function for a relativistic particle, and, as said, are the wanted propertiesif we seek a GFT definition of the canonical/Hamil<strong>to</strong>nian inner product. 4 However,there are several reasons why one may want <strong>to</strong> go beyond this type of structure.(1) From the point of view of a field theory on the simplicial superspace we areadvocating here, the most natural object one would expect a GFT <strong>to</strong> define with its2-point functions is not a canonical inner product, solution of the Hamil<strong>to</strong>nian constraint,but a Green function for it. This is what happens in ordinary QFT, for thefree theory, and in the formal context of continuum third quantization for <strong>Quantum</strong><strong>Gravity</strong>, where the (free theory) Feynman amplitudes correspond <strong>to</strong> the usual pathintegral for <strong>Quantum</strong> <strong>Gravity</strong>, with amplitude given by the exponential of the GRaction [3; 4; 5], which is a Green function for the Hamil<strong>to</strong>nian constraint, and nota solution of the same, in each of its arguments. (2) The orientation of the GFT2-complexes can be given, for Lorentzian models, a causal interpretation [28; 29],and thus the orientation independence of the usual models suggests that one shouldbe able <strong>to</strong> construct other types of models defining causal <strong>Quantum</strong> <strong>Gravity</strong> transitionamplitudes [28; 29] and corresponding GFTs. (3) No clear meaning can begiven from the Hamil<strong>to</strong>nian/canonical perspective <strong>to</strong> the GFT amplitudes for Feynmangraphs beyond the tree level, when spatial <strong>to</strong>pology change is present. For allthese reasons one would like <strong>to</strong> have a more general class of GFT models thatdo depend on the orientation of the GFT Feynman graphs, that can be interpretedconsistently as analogs of causal transition amplitudes of QFT, that are in moredirect contact with usual path integral formulations of (simplicial) gravity, and thatreduce <strong>to</strong> the above type of models when suitably restricted. A class of modelsthat achieves this was constructed in [24]. Here a generalized version of the GFTformalism was defined, for a field φ(g i , s i ) : (G × R) ⊗4 → C:S gen = ∑ μ,α+ ∑ μ144∏∫i=1∑α idg i∫λ {αi ,μ}5!R[ ∏ ( )ds i{φ ] }−μα (g i , s i ) −iμα∂si +∇ i φ μα (g i , s i )i5∏∫ ∫{dg ij ds ij Ph φ μα 1(g 1 j , s 1 j )P h φ μα 2(g 2 j , s 2 j )i̸= j=1GR...P h φ μα 5(g 5 j , s 5 j ) ∏ θ(α i s ij + α j s ji )K ( g ij , g ji ; μ(α i s ij + α j s ji ) )} ,4 In other words, the Feynman amplitudes of these GFT models would correspond not <strong>to</strong> a simplicial versionof the path integral formalism for <strong>Quantum</strong> <strong>Gravity</strong>, but <strong>to</strong> the symmetrized version of the same over oppositespacetime orientations, that indeed gives a path integral definition of solutions of the Hamil<strong>to</strong>nian constrain<strong>to</strong>pera<strong>to</strong>r of canonical <strong>Quantum</strong> <strong>Gravity</strong> [26].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!