12.07.2015 Views

Approaches to Quantum Gravity

Approaches to Quantum Gravity

Approaches to Quantum Gravity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Quantum</strong> <strong>Gravity</strong>: the art of building spacetime 343According <strong>to</strong> (18.3), the quantum fluctuations around this path can then beconsidered small since is small.This is more or less the picture we envisage for our present-day universe in<strong>Quantum</strong> <strong>Gravity</strong>: the universe is of macroscopic size, governed by the classicalequations of motion (the analog of choosing “by hand” (x 1 , t 1 ) and (x 2 , t 2 ) <strong>to</strong> bemacroscopic in the example above), and the small quantum fluctuations are dictatedby the gravitational coupling constant (times /c 3 ).A given configuration x(t) in the path integral for the quantum-mechanical particleis (with probability one) a continuous, nowhere differentiable path, whichmoreover is fractal with Hausdorff dimension two, as we know from the rigorousconstruction of the Wiener measure on the set of parametrized paths. In the caseof <strong>Quantum</strong> <strong>Gravity</strong> we do not have a similar mathematically rigorously definedmeasure on the space of geometries, but it is natural <strong>to</strong> expect that if it exists,a typical geometry in the path integral will be continuous, but nowhere differentiable.By analogy, the piecewise linear geometries seem a good choice if we want<strong>to</strong> approximate the gravitational path integral by a set of geometries and subsequentlytake a limit where the approximation (the cut-off) is removed. Moreover,such simplicial manifolds possess a natural, geometric and coordinate-independentimplementation of the Einstein–Hilbert action. With all local curvature degrees offreedom present (albeit in a discretized fashion), we also expect them <strong>to</strong> be suitably“dense” in the set of all continuous geometries.The spirit is very much that of the standard lattice formulation of quantumfield theory where (flat) spacetime is approximated by a hypercubic lattice. Theultraviolet cut-off in such field theories is given by the lattice spacing, i.e. thelength of all one-dimensional lattice edges. We can in a similar and simple mannerintroduce a diffeomorphism-invariant cut-off in the sum over the piecewise lineargeometries by restricting it <strong>to</strong> the building blocks mentioned earlier. A naturalbuilding block for a d-dimensional spacetime is a d-dimensional equilateral simplexwith side-length a, and the path integral is approximated by performing thesum over all geometries (of fixed <strong>to</strong>pology 3 ) which can be obtained by gluing such3 In classical General Relativity there is no motivation <strong>to</strong> consider spacetimes whose spatial <strong>to</strong>pology changesin time, since their Lorentzian structure is necessarily singular. There is an interesting and long-standing discussionabout whether one should include <strong>to</strong>pology changes in a quantum theory of gravity. However, evenin the case of two-dimensional Euclidean <strong>Quantum</strong> <strong>Gravity</strong>, where the classification of <strong>to</strong>pology changes issimple, the summation over <strong>to</strong>pologies has never been defined non-perturbatively in a satisfac<strong>to</strong>ry way, despitemany attempts, in particular, in so-called non-critical string theory. (However, see [24; 25; 26] for how onemay improve the convergence of the sum in two-dimensional Lorentzian <strong>Quantum</strong> <strong>Gravity</strong> by invoking notjust the <strong>to</strong>pological, but the causal, geometric structure of spacetime.) The situation becomes worse in higherdimensions. For instance, four-dimensional <strong>to</strong>pologies are not classifiable, so what does it mean <strong>to</strong> sum overthem in the path integral? The problem – even in dimension two – is that there are many more geometries ofcomplicated <strong>to</strong>pology than there are of simple <strong>to</strong>pology, with the consequence that any sum over geometrieswill be (i) completely dominated by these complicated <strong>to</strong>pologies, and (ii) plainly divergent in a way which(until now) has made it impossible <strong>to</strong> define the theory non-perturbatively in an unambiguous and physicallysatisfac<strong>to</strong>ry manner. In higher dimensions these problems are <strong>to</strong>tally out of control.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!